Ethical and Legal Issues in Medical Genetics

Published on 16/03/2015 by admin

Filed under Basic Science

Last modified 22/04/2025

Print this page

rate 1 star rate 2 star rate 3 star rate 4 star rate 5 star
Your rating: none, Average: 0 (0 votes)

This article have been viewed 3382 times

CHAPTER 24 Ethical and Legal Issues in Medical Genetics

Ethics is the branch of knowledge that deals with moral principles, which in turn relate to principles of right, wrong, justice, and standards of behavior. Traditionally, the reference points are based on a synthesis of the philosophical and religious views of well-informed, respected, thinking members of society. In this way, a code of practice evolves that is seen as reasonable and acceptable by a majority, which often forms the basis for professional guidelines or regulations. It might be argued that there are no ‘absolutes’ in ethical and moral debates. In complex scenarios, in which there may be competing and conflicting claims to an ethical principle, practical decisions and actions often have to be based on a balancing of duties, responsibilities, and rights. Ethics, like science, is not static but moves on, and in fact the development of the two disciplines is closely intertwined.

Ethical issues arise in all branches of medicine, but human genetics poses particular challenges because genetic identity impinges not just on an individual, but also on close relatives and the extended family, as well as society in general. In the minds of the general public, clinical genetics and genetic counseling can easily be confused with eugenics—defined as the science of ‘improving’ a species through breeding. It is important to stress that the modern specialty of clinical genetics has absolutely nothing in common with the appalling eugenic philosophies that were practiced in Nazi Germany and, to a much lesser extent, elsewhere in Europe and the United States between the two world wars. Emphasis has already been placed on the fundamental principle that genetic counseling is a non-directive and non-judgmental communication process whereby factual knowledge is imparted to facilitate informed personal choice (see Chapter 17). Indeed, clinical geneticists have been pioneers in recent times in practicing and promoting non-paternalism in medicine, and 5% of the original budget for the Human Genome Project was set aside for funding studies into the ethical and social implications of the knowledge gained from the project. Coercion and eugenics certainly have no place in modern medical genetics.

Nevertheless, this subject lends itself to ethical debate, not least because of the new challenges and opportunities provided by discoveries and new technologies in molecular genetics. In this chapter, some of the more controversial and difficult areas are considered. It soon becomes apparent that for many of these issues there is no clearly right or wrong approach and that individual views will vary widely. Sometimes in a clinical setting the best that can be hoped for is to arrive at a mutually acceptable compromise, with an explicit agreement that opposing views are respected and, personal conscience permitting, a patient’s expressed wishes are carried out.

As genetic testing and DNA technologies enter the mainstream of medicine, and awareness of the ethical issues grows and impacts society, so there is a need for some restrictions and protections to be enshrined in law. This chapter therefore touches on some developments in this area. The Western world is becoming increasingly familiar with courts of law making final decisions—for example, in relation to contentious end-of-life issues—and this trend is likely to continue.

General Principles

The time-honored four principles of medical ethics that command wide consensus are listed in Box 24.1. Developed and championed by the American ethicists Tom Beauchamp and James Childress, these principles provide an acceptable framework, although close scrutiny of many difficult dilemmas highlights limitations in these principles and apparent conflicts between them. Everyone involved in clinical genetics will sooner or later be confronted by complex and challenging ethical situations, some of which pose particularly difficult problems with no obvious solution, and certainly no perfect one. Just as patients need to balance risks when making a decision about a treatment option, so the clinician/counselor may need to balance these principles one against the other. A particular difficulty in medical genetics can be the principle of autonomy, given that we all share our genes with our biological relatives. Individual autonomy needs sometimes to be weighed against the principle of doing good, and doing no harm, to close family members.

The Beauchamp and Childress framework of ethical principles is, unsurprisingly, not the only one in use and others have developed them into practical approaches. These include the Jonsen framework (Box 24.2) and the more detailed scheme developed by Mike Parker of Oxford’s Ethox Centre (Box 24.3), which builds on previous proposals. Taken together, these provide a practical approach to clinical ethics, which is an expanding discipline in health care.

Box 24.3

The Ethox Centre Clinical Ethics Framework (Mike Parker)

In practice, the issues that commonly arise in the genetics clinic during any patient contact are outlined below.

Informed Consent

A patient is entitled to an honest and full explanation before any procedure or test is undertaken. Information should include details of the risks, limitations, implications, and possible outcomes of each procedure. In the current climate, with respect to full information and the doctor-patient contract, some form of signed consent is increasingly being obtained for every action that exposes the patient—access to medical records, clinical photography, genetic testing, and storage of DNA. In fact, there is no legal requirement to obtain signed consent for taking a blood test from which DNA is extracted and stored. The issue was addressed by the UK Human Tissue Act 2004. According to the act, DNA does not constitute ‘human tissue’ in the same way as biopsy samples or cellular material, for which formal consent is required, whether the tissue is from the living or the dead. The act does require that consent is formally obtained where cellular material is used to obtain genetic information for another person. In a clinical setting, this must be clearly discussed and documented.

In clinical genetics, many patients who are candidates for clinical examination and genetic testing are children or individuals with learning difficulties who may lack capacity to grant informed consent. Furthermore, the result of any examination or test may have only a small chance of directly benefiting the patient but is potentially very important for family members. Here the law is important. In England and Wales, the Mental Capacity Act of 2005 came into effect in 2007 and applies to adults aged 16 and older. It replaced case law for health (and social) care and there is a legal duty to use the legislation and apply the ‘Test for Capacity’ (Box 24.4) for any relevant decision for people who lack capacity. Decisions must take into account the ‘best interests’ of the patient, but can also embrace the wider interests that relate to the family. In England and Wales, the law allows for an appropriate person appointed by the Court of Protection to act on their behalf, whereas in Scotland it is legally permitted for certain designated adults, including family members, to give consent (or refuse) on behalf of a person lacking capacity.

Ethical Dilemmas in the Genetic Clinic

Prenatal Diagnosis

Many methods are now widely available for diagnosing structural abnormalities and genetic disorders during the first and second trimesters (see Chapter 21). The past 35 to 40 years have seen the first real availability of choice in the context of pregnancy in human history. Not surprisingly, the issue of prenatal diagnosis and subsequent offer of termination of pregnancy raises many difficult issues for individuals and families, and raises serious questions about the way in which society views and cares for both children and adults with disability. In the United Kingdom, termination of pregnancy is permitted up to and beyond 24 weeks’ gestation if the fetus has a lethal condition such as anencephaly, or if there is a serious risk of major physical or mental handicap. For good reason, terms such as ‘serious’ are not defined in the relevant legislation, but this can inevitably lead to controversy over interpretation.

The difficulties surrounding prenatal diagnosis can be illustrated by considering some of the general principles that have already been discussed. At the top of the list comes informed consent. In the United Kingdom, approximately 70% of all pregnancies are monitored for the presence of a neural tube defect by measurement of α-fetoprotein in maternal serum at approximately 16 weeks’ gestation (p. 328). In theory, all women undergoing this test should have a full understanding of its potential implications. This also applies to every woman who is offered a detailed ultrasonographic scan to assess fetal anatomy at around 18 to 20 weeks’ gestation (p. 326). For fully informed consent to be obtained in these situations, it is essential that pregnant women should have access to detailed counseling by unhurried staff members who are knowledgeable, experienced, and sympathetic. In practice this may not always be so; indeed, there is evidence that the quality of information provided varies widely.

The most difficult problems in prenatal diagnosis are those involving autonomy and individual choice. This relates particularly to disease severity and who should make the decision that termination is justified. This can be illustrated by considering the following situations. In the first situation, parents whose first child, a boy, has autism are expecting another baby. They have read that autism is more common in boys than girls, so they request sexing of the fetus with a view to terminating a male fetus but continuing if the sex is female. Overall, however, the risk of having another child with autism is only about 5%. Such a request presents the clinician and counselor with a challenge. There is general agreement that sex selection for purely social reasons is not justified as grounds for termination of pregnancy, nor indeed for embryo selection by preimplantation genetic diagnosis (PGD), although in the United States, it is permissible to perform sex selection by PGD for ‘family balancing’. In the United Kingdom, the general public, through a public consultation process overseen by the Human Fertilization and Embryology Authority (HFEA), has overwhelmingly expressed the view that sex selection for social reasons and family balancing is not acceptable: children should be considered as gifts, not consumer commodities. But what about this situation, when the risk of a second child having autism is low and it cannot be guaranteed that a daughter would not be affected?

Next, consider the unusual but not unprecedented dilemma that arises when parents with an inherited condition indicate that they wish to continue with a pregnancy only if tests show that their unborn baby is also affected. Examples of conditions that could generate a request of this nature include achondroplasia and congenital sensorineural hearing loss. If the family’s autonomy and right to choose is to be respected, then their request should be granted. Many readers of this chapter will be uncomfortable with the suggestion that an unaffected pregnancy should be terminated. This particular scenario illustrates the difficulty of interpretation and defining what is normal.

The issue of autonomy and individual choice can also arise when a fetus is found to have a relatively mild abnormality, such as a non-syndromal cleft lip and palate, for which surgical correction usually achieves an excellent outcome. For some parents, particularly those who themselves have had an unhappy childhood because of being stigmatized for a similar problem, the prospect of having a similarly affected child can be unacceptable. Understandably, medical and nursing staff may feel very uneasy about complying with a request for termination of pregnancy in such situations.

It is inevitable that a subject as emotive as termination of pregnancy will generate controversy, and the ethical dilemmas that arise are not easily resolved. Proponents of choice argue that selective termination should be available, particularly if the alternative involves a lifetime of pain and suffering. More often than not, prenatal diagnostic techniques provide reassurance, and the fact that tests are available provides many couples with the necessary confidence to embark on a pregnancy. Without the option of prenatal tests, these couples might decide against trying to have further children. When viewed in the context of abortion in general, termination on the grounds of fetal abnormality constitutes less than 2% of the total of approximately 200,000 abortions carried out each year in the United Kingdom.

Those who hold opposing views argue on religious, moral or ethical grounds that selective termination is little less than legalized infanticide. Key to the ethical issue here are views on the status and rights of the embryo and fetus. For those who believe that the fertilized egg constitutes full human status, PGD and embryo research are unacceptable. Indeed, logically, for people who hold this belief all in-vitro fertilization (IVF) programs are unacceptable by virtue of generating thousands of spare human embryos to be kept in freezers, most never used. There is also concern that prenatal diagnostic screening programs could lead to a devaluing of the ‘disabled’ and ‘abnormal’ in society (notwithstanding that these terms are difficult to define and all too often used pejoratively), with a possible shift of resources away from their care to the funding of programs aimed at ‘preventing’ their birth. The debate about the ethics of prenatal diagnosis is a fierce one that will become even more difficult when genes are identified for common multifactorial disorders such as depression and schizophrenia. Mutations or polymorphisms in such genes are likely to confer a risk that the fetus will develop the condition as an adult, not that the individual will definitely be affected. The arrival of microarray-CGH technology, and in the future rapid automated genome sequencing, is raising the specter of wide-ranging, affordable antenatal genetic screening, well before we know how to identify all copy number polymorphisms and variants of unknown significance.

The results of public consultation exercises conducted by the Advisory Committee on Genetic Testing (subsumed into the Human Genetics Commission which was abolished in 2010) and the HFEA are reasonably reassuring. The views expressed support the applications of genetics in prenatal testing for serious disorders but concern over wider applications of the techniques. Similarly, research published by the British Social Attitudes survey, in the context of genetics research and gene manipulation for the detection of disease, suggested that the public supports these activities in general but expressed deep reservations for application of the technologies for genetic enhancement. Genetic enhancement, through manipulation of embryos or gametes, strikes at the very heart of what it means to have one’s own identity through natural laws of chance. This, it seems, is a powerful undercurrent in the understanding of who we are as individuals and as a species.

Predictive Testing In Childhood

Understandably, parents sometimes wish to know whether or not a child has inherited the gene for an adult-onset autosomal dominant disorder that runs in the family. It could be argued that this knowledge will help the parents guide their child toward the most appropriate educational and career opportunities and that to refuse their request is a denial of their rights as parents. Similarly, parents may request testing to clarify the status of young healthy children at risk of being carriers of a recessive disorder such as cystic fibrosis. Sometimes this information will have become available as a result of prenatal diagnostic testing.

The problem with agreeing to such a request is that it infringes the child’s own future autonomy. Increasingly, it is felt that testing should be delayed until the child reaches an age at which he or she can make his or her own informed decision. There is also concern about the possible deleterious effects on a child of growing up with the certain knowledge of developing a serious adult-onset hereditary disorder or being a carrier of a recessive disorder, particularly if the tests have proved negative in the child’s other siblings. Such a situation could raise a very real possibility of stigmatization. However, although there is consensus among geneticists that children should not be tested for carrier status, the evidence that such testing causes emotional or psychological harm is weak.

The situation is very different if predictive testing could directly benefit the child by identifying the need for a medical or surgical intervention in childhood. This applies to conditions such as familial hypercholesterolemia (p. 175), for which early dietary management can be introduced, and also to some of the familial cancer-predisposing syndromes (p. 225) for which early screening, and sometimes prophylactic surgery, is indicated. Generally, it is thought that in these situations genetic testing is acceptable at around the time when other screening tests or preventive measures would be initiated.

One of the arguments for not testing children for adult-onset disorders is that parents might view their child differently, perhaps prejudicially, in some way. This type of argument has been voiced in relation to the PGD cases that have selected embryos not only for their negative affection status for Fanconi anemia but also in order to be a potential stem-cell donor for their affected child—so-called ‘savior siblings’. Those objecting to this use of technology cite a utilitarian, or instrumental, attitude toward the child created in this way. Furthermore, the child so created has no choice about whether to be a tissue-matched donor for the sick sibling. Will the child eventually feel ‘used’ by the parents, and how might he or she feel if the treatment fails and the sick sibling dies? At present these questions are imponderables because most children created for this purpose are too young to tell how they feel—the first successful case was in the United States in 2000. The numbers of such children will be very small for the foreseeable future.

Implications for the Immediate Family (Inadvertent Testing or Testing by ‘Proxy’)

A positive test result in an individual can have major implications for close antecedent relatives who themselves may not wish to be informed of their disease status. For example, consider Huntington disease (HD), for which direct mutation analysis is available. A young man age 20 years requests predictive testing before starting his family; his fears are based on a confirmed diagnosis in his 65-year-old paternal grandfather. Predictive testing would be relatively straightforward were it not for the fact that his father, who is obviously at a prior risk of 1 in 2, specifically does not wish to know whether he will develop the disease.

Thus the young man has raised the difficult question of how to comply with his request without inadvertently carrying out a predictive test on his father. A negative result in the young man leaves the situation unchanged for his father. However, a positive result in the son might be difficult to conceal from an observant father; and the son will know that his father will develop the disease if he has not done so already.

There is no easy solution to this particular problem. In the guidelines drawn up in 1994 for predictive testing in HD it was concluded that ‘every effort should be made by the counselors and the persons concerned to come to a satisfactory solution’, with the rider that ‘if no consensus can be reached the right of the adult child to know should have priority over the right of the parent not to know’.

Implications for the Extended Family

It is widely agreed that the identification of a condition that could have implications for other family members should lead to the offer of tests for the extended family. This applies particularly to balanced translocations and serious X-linked recessive disorders. In the case of translocations, this is sometimes referred to as translocation chasing. For an autosomal recessive disorder such as cystic fibrosis, the term ‘cascade screening’ is applied (p. 304).

The main ethical problem that arises here is that of confidentiality. A carrier of a translocation or serious X-linked recessive disorder is usually urged to alert close family relatives to the possibility that they could also be carriers and therefore at risk of having affected children. Alternatively, permission can be sought for members of the genetics team to make these approaches. Occasionally a patient, for whatever reason, will refuse to allow this information to be disseminated.

Faced with this situation, what should the clinical geneticist do? In practice most clinical geneticists would try to convince their patient of the importance of offering information and tests to relatives, possibly by providing an explanation of the consequences and ill-feeling that could arise in the future if a relative was to have an affected child whose birth could have been avoided. In most cases, skilled and sensitive counseling will lead to a satisfactory solution. Ultimately, however, many clinical geneticists would opt to respect their patient’s confidentiality rather than break the trust that forms a cornerstone of the traditional doctor-patient relationship. Not all would agree, and where the application of this standard could result in damage or morbidity to other family members, the clinician might seek to persuade the individual to disclose the medical/genetic information. This view is backed up by the statements of authoritative working parties, such as the Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Sometimes it is possible to draw the issue to the attention of the general practitioner of the family member at risk—he or she might be well placed to open the issue up in a sensitive way.

Informed Consent in Genetic Research

All individuals who agree to undergo genetic testing in a service context are obviously entitled to a full and clear explanation of what the test involves and how the results could have implications for both themselves and other family members. Vigorous efforts are usually made to ensure that these basic principles are adhered to, particularly when predictive testing for serious late-onset genetic disorders is being undertaken.

The issues relating to informed consent when participating in genetic research are just as complex. Many people are perfectly willing to hold out their arm for a blood test which might ‘help others’, particularly if they have personal experience of a serious disorder in their own family. However, few will have given any serious thought to the possible ramifications of their simple act of altruism. For example, it is unlikely that they will ever have considered whether their sample will be tested anonymously, who will be informed of the result, or whether other tests will be carried out on stored DNA in the future as new techniques are developed. These concerns, among others (Box 24.5), have prompted the US National Institutes of Health Office of Protection from Research Risks to draw up proposals on the steps that should be taken to try to ensure that all aspects of informed consent are addressed when samples are collected for genetic research. Just as signed consent for genetic testing and storage of DNA has become routine in the service setting (although not a legal requirement under the UK Human Tissue Act 2004), similar procedures should be adhered to in a research setting.

Ethical Dilemmas and the Public Interest

Recent progress in genetics, most notably in the area of molecular testing, has brought the ethical debate into a much wider public arena. Topics such as insurance, forensic science and DNA databases, patenting, gene therapy, population screening, cloning, stem-cell research, and hybrids, are now rightly viewed as being of major societal, commercial, and political importance, and perhaps not surprisingly they feature prominently in media discussion. All of these subjects affect the specialty of medical genetics and each of these will now be considered in turn.

Genetics and Insurance

The availability of predictive tests for disorders of adult onset that convey a risk for chronic ill health, and possibly reduced life expectancy, has led to concern about the extent to which the results of these tests should be revealed to outside agencies, especially insurance companies providing life cover, private health care, and critical illness and disability income. For insurance arranged through an employer, in theory adverse genetic tests might compromise career prospects.

The life insurance industry is competitive and profit driven. Private insurance is based on ‘mutuality’, whereby risks are pooled for individuals in similar circumstances. In contrast, public health services are based on the principle of ‘solidarity’, whereby health provision for everyone is funded from general taxation. It is understandable that the life insurance industry is concerned that individuals who receive a positive predictive test result will take out large policies without revealing their true risk status. This is sometimes referred to as ‘antiselection’ or ‘adverse selection’. On the other hand, the genetics community is concerned that individuals who test positive will become victims of discrimination, and perhaps uninsurable. This concern extends to those with a family history of a late-onset disorder, who might be refused insurance unless they undergo predictive testing.

The possibility that DNA testing will create an uninsurable ‘genetic underclass’ led to the introduction of legislation in parts of the United States aimed at limiting the use of genetic information by health insurers. In 1996 this culminated in President Clinton signing The Health Insurance Portability and Accountability Act, which expressly prevented employer-based health plans from refusing coverage on genetic grounds when a person changes employment. In the United Kingdom, this whole arena was considered in 1995 by the House of Commons Science and Technology Committee, which recommended that a Human Genetics Advisory Commission be established to overview developments in human genetics. In 1997 this Advisory Commission (subsumed into the Human Genetics Commission which was abolished in 2010) recommended that applicants for life insurance should not have to disclose the results of any genetic test to a prospective insurer and that a moratorium on disclosure of results should last for at least 2 years until genetic testing had been carefully evaluated.

Inevitably, the Association of British Insurers (ABI) had a view. In the 1999 revision of its Code of Practice, the ABI reiterated its view that applicants should not be asked to undergo genetic testing and that existing genetic test results need not be disclosed in applications for mortgage-related life assurance up to a total of £100,000. In 2005 the UK government negotiated an agreement with the ABI to extend restriction on the use of predictive genetic tests by insurers to November 2011. The document, entitled ‘Concordat and Moratorium on Genetics and Insurance’ (Box 24.6), stated that no one will be required to disclose the result of a predictive genetic test unless first approved by the government’s Genetics and Insurance Committee (GAIC). The GAIC approved only one application—for HD for amounts greater than £500,000—and the body was abolished in 2009.

These issues are likely to come under renewed scrutiny in the future. Where various combinations of polymorphisms convey susceptibility to common disorders of adult life, large swathes of the population could find themselves at the mercy of a profit-driven, commercially-focused insurance industry. The medical genetics community therefore has an advocacy role to ensure that the genetically disadvantaged, through no fault of their own, do not face discrimination when seeking health care or long-term life insurance. These are powerful arguments favoring retention of the principles of the UK National Health Service.

Forensic Science and DNA Databases

The existence of the police-controlled National DNA Database in the UK has been hotly debated as an issue of personal privacy. The use of DNA fingerprinting in criminal investigations, to the tune of approximately 10,000 cases per annum, is now so sophisticated that there is a natural desire on the part of law enforcers to be able to identify the DNA fingerprint for anyone in the general population. Furthermore, techniques have been developed, called DNA boost, to generate profiles of individuals from samples where the DNA of two or more persons is mixed. The UK’s National DNA Database, which once contained material solely from sentenced offenders, has expanded rapidly and is now the largest of any country, containing information on more than 5 million people (0.8% of the population), including an estimated 1 million with no criminal conviction; this compares with 0.5% of the population in the United States. For certain types of crime, whole sections of a community are invited to come forward to give a sample of DNA so that they can be eliminated from enquiries. However, with significant numbers of DNA samples from children on the database, including that of at least one infant, the police came under political pressure in 2009 to scrap ‘innocent’ profiles after a declaration by the European Court of Human Rights that to hold the profiles of innocents indefinitely was a breach of privacy.

The National DNA Database is huge, but so too are the collections for big population studies, such as ALSPAC (Avon Longitudinal Study of Parents and Children) or the UK Biobank project. As research, these samples will have been rigorously consented, but it is essential for safeguards to be built into the use that is made of DNA collections such as these, and access to them. Debate will certainly continue on the use and misuse of personal genetic data.

Gene Patenting and the Human Genome Project

The controversy surrounding the patenting of naturally occurring human DNA sequences, whether complete genes or expressed sequence tags, neatly encapsulates the conflict between harsh commercial realism and altruistic academic idealism. As illustrations of the levels of investment, it is noteworthy that the rights to one gene associated with obesity were sold in 1995 for $70 million, whereas in 1997 DeCODE, the Icelandic genomics company at the center of the controversy regarding national assent, sold the potential rights to 12 genes, possibly associated with common complex diseases, to Hoffman-La Roche for $200 million. On the one hand, biotechnology companies that have invested heavily in molecular research can reasonably argue that they and their shareholders are entitled to benefit from the fruits of their labors. Biotechnology research is indeed expensive, and the realistic view is that commercial companies must at least cover their costs (otherwise they cease to exist) but preferably make a fair return on investments. The idealistic view argues that the human genome represents humankind’s ‘common heritage’ and that information gained through the Human Genome Project, or other molecular research, should be freely available for all to benefit, thus maintaining the ethical principle of equity of access. Proponents of the latter cite alleged exploitation of patients and communities who have donated their blood samples for research, little realizing that their generosity could be exploited for financial gain. This is amply illustrated by the furor surrounding the proposed use (or abuse) of a centralized medical database of the entire Icelandic population to help identify ‘polygenes’ for potential commercial gain. There have been some high-profile court cases over the issue in the United States.

The legal issues are complex and, not surprisingly, the international community has struggled to identify satisfactory solutions. With the exception of the United States, most national regulatory bodies prohibit payment for the procurement of human genetic material, but their views on patenting are much less well defined. In recent years many important human genes have been patented, and companies such as Myriad Genetics in the United States sought to impose their exclusive licence for genetic testing for BRCA1 and BRCA2 (p. 224). In fact, in 2004 the European Patent Office revoked the patent, denying Myriad a license fee from every BRCA test undertaken in Europe, and thereby setting a precedent for other contentious cases. Gene patents may concern single-gene disorders, such as the BRCA genes, but increasingly commercial companies are offering a range of ‘direct to consumer’ tests, consisting of the analysis of a range of polymorphisms, with the promise of predicting the future risk of ill health from common disorders. These companies are often less than candid about the precise tests offered, and their validation, all of which runs counter to the spirit of scientific enquiry and evidence-based medicine.

Gene Therapy

One of the most exciting aspects of recent progress in molecular biology is the prospect of successful gene therapy (p. 350), although it is obviously disappointing that this potential has not yet been realized. It is understandable that both the general public and the health care professions should be concerned about the possible side effects and abuse of gene therapy. Frequent reference has been made to the ‘slippery slope’ argument, whereby to take the first step leads incrementally and inevitably to uncontrolled experimentation. To address these anxieties, advisory or regulatory committees have been established in several countries to assess the practical and ethical aspects of gene therapy research programs.

Concern centers around two fundamental issues. The first relates to the practical aspects of ensuring informed consent on the part of patients who wish to participate in gene therapy research. Adult patients and parents of children affected by otherwise incurable conditions may be desperate to participate in gene therapy research. Consequently they may disregard the possible hazards of what is essentially a new, untried, and unproven therapeutic approach. In the United Kingdom, the Committee on the Ethics of Gene Therapy recommended that, until shown to be safe, all gene therapy programs should be subjected to careful scrutiny by research ethics committees. In addition, a national supervisory body, the Gene Therapy Advisory Committee (GTAC), was established to review all proposals to conduct gene therapy in humans and to monitor ongoing trials, thus safeguarding patients’ rights and confidentiality.

Second, gene therapy generates concern about potential eugenic applications. The GTAC recommended that genetic modification involving the germline should be prohibited, and limited to somatic cells, to prevent the possibility of newly modified genes being transmitted to future generations. Somatic cell gene therapy should be used only to try to treat serious diseases, and not to alter human characteristics, such as intelligence or athletic prowess for example.

Population Screening

Population screening programs offering carrier detection for common autosomal recessive disorders, have been in operation for many years (p. 318), and in many cases well received (e.g., thalassemia and Tay-Sachs disease). This was not so with respect to neonatal screening for α1 antitrypsin deficiency in Scandinavia, which was abandoned because it proved stressful. Such is the progress in comparative genome analysis that it will be technically possible to compare the genome of the unborn baby with that of its parents; de novo differences may represent mutations that would lead to serious disease and it has been proposed that the technique is offered to couples undergoing PGD. Chorionic villus tissue could also be analyzed in this way, and even free fetal DNA from maternal blood eventually. The ethical problem relates to the range of diseases that might be tested this way, and the choices couples might face.

With respect to screening programs that detect carrier status for disease, the issues are slightly different. Early efforts to introduce sickle-cell carrier detection in North America were largely unsuccessful because of misinformation, discrimination, and stigmatization. Also, pilot studies assessing the responses to cystic fibrosis (CF) carrier screening in white populations yielded conflicting results (p. 321). These experiences illustrate the importance of informed consent and the difficulties of ensuring both autonomy and informed choice. For example, CF screening in the United Kingdom has been implemented as part of neonatal screening. Although aimed at identifying babies with CF, the screening detects a proportion who are simply carriers, but obviously newborn infants cannot make an informed choice. Consequently, some pilot studies have focused on adults and their responses to the offer of carrier testing, either from their general practitioner or at the antenatal clinic. This has raised the vexed question of whether an offer from a respected family doctor could be interpreted as an implicit recommendation to participate, and such an approach yields a higher acceptance rate than a casual written invitation to attend for screening at a future date. This begs the question as to whether, depending on the approach, individuals feel pressured to undergo a test that they do not necessarily want.

It is, therefore, important that even the most well-intended offer of carrier detection should be worded carefully to ensure that participation is entirely voluntary. Full counseling in the event of a positive result is also essential to minimize the risk of any feeling of stigmatization or genetic inferiority.

In population screening, confidentiality is also important. Many will not wish their carrier status to be known by classmates or colleagues at work. The issue of confidentiality will be particularly difficult for individuals found by genetic testing to be susceptible to a medical problem through environmental industrial hazards, which could lead to employment discrimination (p. 367). These anxieties led in 1995 to the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission in the United States issuing a guideline that allows for anyone denied employment because of disease susceptibility to claim protection under the Americans with Disabilities Act.

Cloning and Stem Cell Research

Dolly the sheep, born in July 1996 at Roslin, near Edinburgh, was the first mammal to be cloned from an adult cell, and when her existence was announced about 6 months later, the world suddenly became intensely interested in cloning. Dolly was ‘conceived’ by fusing individual mammary gland cells with unfertilized eggs from which the nucleus had been removed; 277 attempts failed before a successful pregnancy ensued. It was immediately assumed that the technology would sooner or later lead to a cloned human being and there have been some unsubstantiated bogus claims to this effect. In fact, there has been widespread rejection of any move toward human reproductive cloning, with strong statements emanating from politicians, religious leaders, and scientists. Experiments with animals have continued to have a very poor success rate, and for this reason alone no rational person is advocating ‘experiments’ in humans. In some cloned animals, the features have suggested possible defects in genomic imprinting. Dolly died prematurely from lung disease in February 2003 and she had a number of characteristics suggesting she was not biologically normal.

Lessons have been learned from Dolly in relation to cell nuclear replacement technology and this has, potentially, opened the door to understanding more about cell differentiation. The focus has therefore shifted to therapeutic cloning using stem cells, and to the prospects this holds with respect to human disease. If stem cells were subjected to nuclear transfer from a patient in need, they might be stimulated to grow into any tissue type, perhaps in unlimited quantities and genetically identical to the patient, thus avoiding rejection. To date there have been a number of successes and the potential possibilities are legion for degenerative disease and repair of damage from trauma and burns.

The main ethical difficulty arises in relation to the source of stem cells. No one voices serious ethical difficulties in relation to stem cells harvested from the fully formed person, whether taken from the umbilical cord or the mature adult, and there have been significant advances using these sources. But a strong school of scientific opinion maintains that there is no substitute for studying embryonic stem cells to understand how cells differentiate from primitive into more complex types. In 2005 the UK Parliament moved swiftly to approve an extension to research on early human embryos for this purpose. Research on human embryos up to 14 days of age was already permitted under the Human Fertilization and Embryology Act 1990. The United Kingdom therefore became one of the most attractive places to work in stem-cell research because, although regulated, it is legal. Publicly funded research of this kind was not permitted in the United States until a change of political direction in 2009. Progress has been painfully slow for those engaged in this work, and the focus shifted to the creation of animal-human (‘human-admixed’) hybrids and chimeras because of the poor supply and quality of human oocytes (usually ‘leftovers’ from infertility treatment) for use in nuclear cell transfer. In the United Kingdom, Newcastle was granted a license to collect fresh eggs for stem-cell research from egg donors in return for a reduction in the cost of IVF treatment, a decision greeted with alarm in some quarters. This group was also the first, in 2005, to create a human blastocyst after nuclear transfer.

Those who object to the use of embryonic stem cells believe it is not only treating the human embryo with disrespect and tampering with the sanctity of life, but also could lead eventually to reproductive cloning. In fact, the Human Fertilization and Embryology Act of 1990 permits the creation of human embryos for research, but very few have been created since the HFEA began granting licenses. This Act of Parliament has been reviewed and updated to accommodate new developments, and came into effect in 2009. The main provisions are listed in Box 24.7 and will continue to generate contentious ethical debate.

Conclusion

Advances in human molecular genetics and cell biology generate major issues in medical ethics. Each new discovery brings new challenges and raises new dilemmas for which there are usually no easy answers. On a global scale the computerization of medical records, together with the widespread introduction of genetic testing, makes it essential that safeguards are introduced to ensure that fundamental principles such as privacy and confidentiality are maintained. Members of the medical genetics community will continue to play a pivotal role in trying to balance the needs of their patients and families with the demands of an increasingly cost-conscious society and a commercially driven biotechnology industry. Cost-benefit arguments can be persuasive in cold financial terms but take no account of the fundamental human and social issues that are often involved. The medical genetics community must take an advocacy role to ensure that the interests of their patients and families take precedence, and toward that end it is hoped that this chapter, and indeed the rest of this book, can make a positive contribution.

Further Reading

American Society of Human Genetics Report. Statement on informed consent for genetic research. Am J Hum Genet. 1996;59:471-474.

The statement of the American Society of Human Genetics Board of Directors on the issues relating to informed consent in genetic research.

Association of British Insurers. Genetic testing. ABI Code of Practice. London, UK: ABI, London; 1999.

A formal statement of the principles and practice adopted by the British insurance industry with regard to genetic testing.

Baily MA, Murray TH, editors. Ethics and newborn genetic screening: new technologies, new challenges. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore, 2009.

A multiauthor volume with a focus on the health economics of newborn screening and distributive justice.

British Medical Association. Human genetics. Choice and responsibility. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press; 1998.

A comprehensive, wide-ranging report produced by a BMA medical ethics committee steering group on the ethical issues raised by genetics in clinical practice.

Bryant J, Baggott la Velle L, Searle J, editors. Bioethics for scientists. Chichester, UK: John Wiley, 2002.

A multiauthor text of wide scope with many contributions relevant to medical genetics.

Buchanan A, Daniels N, Wikler D, Brock DW. From chance to choice: genetics and justice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press; 2000.

An acclaimed book, intellectually rigorous and wide-ranging, addressing issues related to our knowledge of the human genome.

Clarke A, editor. The genetic testing of children. Oxford, UK: Bios Scientific, 1997.

A comprehensive multiauthor text dealing with this important subject.

Clothier Committee. Report of the Committee on the Ethics of Gene Therapy. London, UK: HMSO; 1992.

Recommendations of the committee chaired by Sir Cecil Clothier on the ethical aspects of somatic cell and germline gene therapy.

Collins FS. Shattuck lecture—medical and societal consequences of the human genome project. N Engl J Med. 1999;341:28-37.

A contemporary overview of the Human Genome Project with emphasis on its possible ethical and social implications.

Harper PS, Clarke AJ. Genetics society and clinical practice. Oxford, UK: Bios Scientific; 1997.

A thoughtful account of the important ethical and social aspects of recent developments in clinical genetics.

Human Genetics Commission. Inside information: balancing interests in the use of personal genetic data. London, UK: Department of Health; 2002.

A detailed working party report by the Human Genetics Commission covering the use and abuse of personal genetic information.

Jonsen AR, Siegler M, Winslade WJ. Clinical ethics: a practical approach to ethical decisions in clinical medicine, 3rd edn. New York: McGraw-Hill; 1992.

The key reference that outlines the Jonsen framework for decision-making in clinical ethics.

Knoppers BM. Status, sale and patenting of human genetic material: an international survey. Nat Genet. 1999;22:23-26.

An article written in the light of a landmark legal and social policy document, the ‘Directive on the Legal Protection of Biotechnology Inventions’, from the European Parliament, 1998.

Knoppers BM, Chadwick R. Human genetic research: emerging trends in ethics. Nat Rev Genet. 2005;6:75-79.

An overview of current international policies on gene patenting.

McInnis MG. The assent of a nation: genetics and Iceland. Clin Genet. 1999;55:234-239.

A critical review of the complex ethical issues raised by the decision of the Icelandic government to collaborate in genetic research with a biotechnology company.

Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Genetic screening: ethical issues. London, UK: Nuffield Council on Bioethics; 1993.

A very helpful document for professional guidance.

Nuffield Council on Bioethics. Mental disorders and genetics: the ethical context. London, UK: Nuffield Council on Bioethics; 1998.

A further detailed document dealing with genetic issues in the context of mental health.

Pokorski RJ. Insurance underwriting in the genetic era. Am J Hum Genet. 1997;60:205-216.

A detailed account of the issues surrounding the use of genetic tests by the insurance industry.

Royal College of Physicians, Royal College of Pathologists, British Society of Human Genetics: Consent and Confidentiality in Genetic Practice. Guidance on genetic testing and sharing genetic information. Report of the Joint Committee on Medical Genetics. London, UK: RCP, RCPath, BSHG; 2006.

A detailed working party report that considers confidentiality issues, especially in the context of the Human Tissue Act 2004.