8 Ethics in perianesthesia nursing
Understanding ethics
The terms ethics and morality, although obviously related, are distinct. Ethics is derived from the Greek root ethos, meaning “character.”1 Morality or morals is derived from the Latin word mores or moralis, meaning “customs, character, or habit.”1 The ancient terms have a shared meaning. Today, persons engaged in the formal discipline of ethical reflection have a more distinct understanding. Beauchamp and Childress understand ethics as a “generic term for various ways of understanding and examining the moral life” and morality as “norms about right or wrong human conduct that are so widely shared that they form a stable (although usually incomplete) social consensus.”2 Morality informs persons in society as to what behavior or conduct may be considered good or right. Questions of morality include: What is the right thing to do in this circumstance? How should I act in this situation?
The goal of ethical reflection, particularly in health care, has the practical function of assisting individuals or groups in the resolution of moral dilemmas. A dilemma occurs when one is faced with a choice between two or more equally desirable but mutually exclusive options. A moral dilemma is present when a moral obligation exists on both sides of the choice to perform or refrain from performing an action and ethical reasons can be found to support either of the alternatives.3 The essence of a moral dilemma is conflict. That is, a moral dilemma occurs when an individual or society experiences a conflict between competing values, duties, and obligations in a given situation.
The emergence of bioethics
In the post-World War II period, a social process that had been under way for some time reached its culmination: the doctor turned into a stranger, and the hospital became a strange institution. Doctors became a group apart from their patients and from society as well, encapsulated in a very isolated and isolating universe.4
Paradigmatic cases
In addition to the larger social movements, the history of the development of bioethics has been fueled by noteworthy medical and legal cases. These cases are significant for leading to profound changes in the way similar medical cases would forever be viewed. These cases reshaped health policy and law and reformed ethical practices in the way other patients in similar circumstances would be treated. The cases led to a different way of perceiving and valuing the moral obligations owed to patients by physicians, researchers, and other health care professionals.
Research with human subjects
Among the most sweeping reform in the second half of the twentieth century was in the arena of medical research with human subjects. For much of medicine’s history, the improvement of care for patients has been through the trial-and-error method of experimentation. Few therapies, when initially applied, had any guarantee of success, and some were fraught with the risk of further injury or debilitation to the patient. Early medical researchers were practicing physicians whose small-scale experiments were conducted solely for therapeutic benefit. The goal of experimentation was undertaken not as much to benefit future patients as to heal the very individual under the immediate care of the practicing physician.5 Most research was, at least in its intent, benevolent and humanistic with the Hippocratic ideal of “doing no harm” providing the guiding norm of the experimenter’s conduct. Nonetheless, two key events revealed how flagrantly this norm can be ignored when the focus shifts to utilitarian goals other than the safety and welfare of humans.
Nazi Germany will forever be remembered for war crimes committed against the human race. Millions of victims lost their lives not only to the actual military conflict of World War II but also to the mass exterminations of innocent members of “undesirable” ethnic groups and other minorities. The techniques for these exterminations were perfected by Nazi physicians whose gruesome acts were later publicly revealed in the Nuremberg war criminal trials and documented by American observer Dr. Leo Alexander.6 The trials revealed how physicians and administrators conspired to engage in medical experiments, such as forced sterilizations, poisonings, the infliction of simulated combat injuries, exposure to infections and extreme weather conditions, and ultimately the refinement of euthanasia techniques on those deemed mentally or physically “defective.” There were approximately 275,000 victims over a 10-year span of time. After these staggering revelations, an international tribunal of judges developed what is known as the Nuremberg Code, a statement of 10 principles that govern the ethical conduct of medical experimentation with human subjects. At the heart of the code is that the “voluntary consent of the human subject is absolutely essential” and that freedom from coercion, force, duress, or deception be a condition of participation in any form of experimentation. Expanding the moral framework for the conduct of medical research in the Nuremberg Code, the World Medical Association adopted the Helsinki Declaration in 1964.
Unfortunately, the efforts of Nuremberg and Helsinki did not end the problems with human research. Even within the United States, these important principles did not filter into the consciousness or conduct of physician experimenters, which became all too apparent in the infamous research project now known as the Tuskegee Syphilis Study. From 1932 to 1972, the U. S. Public Health Service (USPHS), later known as the Centers for Disease Control and Prevention (CDC), engaged in a research study that involved 400 African American men in Macon County, Alabama. During the course of 40 years, what began as a small time-limited project to improve the treatment of syphilis among poor minorities expanded into a full-blown plan marked by deception and discrimination that yielded no new information about the disease and offered no bona fide treatment for subjects.7 When the study first began in the early 1930s, the treatment for syphilis consisted of a difficult regimen of arsenic and mercury vaccinations. Although the treatment offered some control, this method proved to be no definitive cure for the illness. The study was initiated with hopes of understanding the disease and finding the definitive cure, but evolved merely into an observation of how the disease progressed through its various stages, culminating in death in many cases.
Participants in the study were led to believe that they were being provided real treatment for what the physician researchers called bad blood, a euphemistic term for any kind of blood-related condition. Treatment amounted essentially to various placebos combined with painful nontherapeutic spinal taps. Subjects were induced to participate in the study through the offer of free treatment, meals, and transportation. Free burial insurance was promised on the condition that the research subjects permit an autopsy on their deaths for documentation of the effects of the end stages of the disease. Even after World War II, when the curative antibiotic of penicillin became widely available, subjects of the study were prohibited from receiving it so that researchers might continue to track the disease’s effects on the unsuspecting subjects’ bodies. The deception and coercion continued until USPHS investigator Peter Buxtun learned of the project from a colleague. Frustrated in his attempts to end the study by working within the USPHS, Buxtun turned to the press, and reporter Jean Heller broke the story in July 1972.8
The public and political outcry that followed the revelation of the study culminated in its immediate suspension and Congressional passage of the Federal Research Act of 1974, which created two significant entities.9 First, the act established what is now known as the Office for Human Research Protections, which mandates that all institutions that receive federal funding for research with human subjects maintain institutional review boards with oversight for the safety and ethical treatment of research subjects. Second, the act established the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The commission, composed of physicians, researchers, attorneys, theologians, and philosophers, was assigned to craft guidelines that would serve as a moral foundation for future human research regulation.5 By 1979, the commission had arrived at a policy statement known as the Belmont Report.10 The report highlighted three basic ethical principles that guide all medical research involving humans in the United States. The principle of respect for persons requires that participation in research be based on the voluntary informed consent of the subject of the study. The principle of beneficence calls for a comprehensive risk and benefit assessment that weighs the potential harm against the potential benefit to the current subjects or future patients. The principle of justice requires that research subjects be chosen equitably (unlike Tuskegee) and that a fundamental fairness in both benefits gained and risks incurred be shared by research participants. Justice also requires that the more vulnerable members of society, such as children, prisoners, pregnant women, and the mentally challenged, be given added protection in research.
More recently, President Barack Obama authorized the Presidential Commission for the Study of Bioethical Issues to conduct a thorough review of domestic and international regulations on human subjects research to determine whether current rules still provide adequate protection. This directive occurs following the new revelations of unethical research in Guatemala from 1946 to 1948 in the U.S. Public Health Services Sexually Transmitted Diseases Inoculation Study.11
End-of-life cases
Controversial patient care cases involving end-of-life decision making hold a prominent place in the development of the bioethics movement. Three cases are particularly noteworthy; all involved young women, each of whom was severely incapacitated and unable to participate in decisions regarding life-sustaining therapy. The first landmark case is that of Karen Ann Quinlan.12 Karen was a 21-year-old woman in New Jersey who, in 1975, suffered a severe anoxic brain injury after an accidental overdose of alcohol and drugs. Karen never regained consciousness and remained dependent on a ventilator for breathing and a feeding tube for nutrition and hydration. Eventually, she was given the diagnosis of a persistent vegetative state (PVS), a neurologic condition characterized by a “complete unawareness of the self and the environment, accompanied by sleep-wake cycles with either complete or partial preservation of the hypothalamic and brainstem autonomic functions.”13 Patients with PVS display “eyes open” unconsciousness and may have gross involuntary movements, but do not respond to external stimuli or engage in any purposeful activity. After some months, Karen’s parents came to the realization that their daughter would likely never regain consciousness or the ability to have any meaningful interaction with others. Following what they believed would be her own wishes, they asked physicians to remove the ventilator and allow Karen to die a natural death. Karen’s physicians adamantly opposed this idea, believing this to be an act of euthanasia, or worse, murder. Karen’s parents then petitioned the courts, and her case eventually came before the New Jersey Supreme Court. The Supreme Court ruled in the parents’ favor on the basis that Karen had a fundamental right to privacy and the right not to have treatment continued against her will. The Court wrote that “the State’s interest (to preserve life) weakens and the individual’s right to privacy grows as the degree of bodily invasion increases and the prognosis grows dim. Ultimately there comes a point at which the individual’s rights overcome the State’s interest.”12 Physicians slowly weaned Karen from the ventilator while continuing her tube feedings and hydration (Karen’s parents never asked for the removal of the tube). Remarkably, Karen lived an additional 10 years before she died in a nursing home in 1986.
A second landmark case is that of Nancy Cruzan, a case sometimes referred to as the first “right to die” case to go before the United States Supreme Court.14 In 1983, Nancy was a 24-year-old woman who lost control of her vehicle on an icy road late one night in Missouri. She was found lying face down in a ditch after being ejected from her overturned car. Nancy had stopped breathing and had no detectable heartbeat for a brief period of time. Rescue personnel intervened to restore her respiratory and cardiac function. Like Karen Ann Quinlan, Nancy had had an anoxic brain injury that led to the eventual diagnosis of a PVS. Nancy was eventually transferred from an acute care setting to a rehabilitation facility where, despite years of effort, no improvements were seen in her condition. Unlike Karen Ann, Nancy was not dependent on a ventilator but was similarly sustained with a gastrostomy tube for feeding and hydration. Four years after her injury, Nancy’s parents asked physicians to remove the feeding tube with the understanding that Nancy would die. They contended that Nancy had remarked about never wanting to be artificially sustained if she could not be “at least halfway normal.”14 Physicians resisted, and Nancy’s parents turned to the courts for help. The Supreme Court of Missouri ruled against them with the argument that sufficient evidence of Nancy’s true wishes did not exist to justify the withdrawal of life support, particularly in light of the consequence of death. Denial of the Cruzans’ wishes on Nancy’s behalf led to an appeal to the U.S. Supreme Court and set the stage for one of the most famous medical legal cases in U.S. history.
The Cruzan case, and the memory of the Quinlan case before it, propelled the creation of federal legislation designed for individuals to state their desire to refuse life-sustaining treatment under the conditions set forth by the Supreme Court, even if rendered incompetent and unable to communicate. The Patient Self-Determination Act of 1990 established on a national level the legitimacy of previously written advance directives as valid legal expressions of an individual’s desire for no treatment in end-of-life circumstances.15 These advance directives, often referred to as living wills (and in many states including durable power of attorney for health care decisions), in theory meet the “clear and convincing” evidence standard required by the U.S. Supreme Court. Currently, all 50 states recognize and honor some form of written advance directives. However, problems persist in these difficult cases in both the interpretation of generalized written statements and the infrequency of use among the public.16,17 As the next case shows, the absence of clear communication and understanding among family members over end-of-life wishes in medical care sometimes yields disastrous consequences.
The case of Terri Schiavo is the most recent of the series of tragic end-of-life cases to be pushed onto the national stage.18,19 Terri was a 26-year-old woman in 1990 when she had a cardiac arrest most likely as a result of an electrolyte imbalance from an ongoing eating disorder. Like Quinlan and Cruzan before her, she had a severe anoxic injury that rendered her a total care patient in a PVS for 15 years, dependent on a percutaneous endoscopic gastrostomy tube for nutrition and hydration. Early on in her care, Terri’s husband, Michael, and her parents, Bob and Mary Schindler, were united in efforts to keep Terri alive and restore her to some level of conscious functioning. Within a few years, Michael came to the conclusion that Terri would not make any recovery and sought to remove the feeding tube to allow Terri to die. The Schindlers, deeply religious, vehemently opposed this request. They believed that removal of the tube was an act of murder and that continued aggressive effort could restore Terri to wakefulness. The Schindlers also questioned the diagnosis of PVS; they believed that Terri both recognized and communicated with them in her own limited way.
Fundamental disagreement between Michael and the Schindlers over Terri’s fate led to a bitter and international public dispute waged in the courts for more than a decade. The Schindlers petitioned to have Michael removed as Terri’s guardian and garnered the support of the Florida state legislature and Governor Jeb Bush, who signed a one-time stay forbidding the removal of the feeding tube pending further legal appeal. On three separate instances, the U.S. Supreme Court refused to hear the case, each time affirming the appropriateness of lower court findings in favor of Michael Schiavo. In the end, Michael’s position as Terri’s guardian was upheld and the courts allowed the removal of the percutaneous endoscopic gastrostomy tube. Terri died on March 31, 2005, with her husband at her side. After her death, Michael permitted, at the request of the Schindlers, a neuropathologic autopsy that revealed severe atrophy of the brain. The official cause of death by the medical examiner was listed as “complications from anoxic encephalopathy.”20
The cases of Quinlan, Cruzan, and Schiavo reveal the ongoing struggle that clinicians and families face in making decisions on behalf of patients with incapacitated conditions. The legacy of these cases highlights the continuing difficulties in withdrawing or withholding treatment in the care of patients with life-threatening conditions and little or no hope of recovery. A lack of public consensus has limited the development of social and institutional policy to guide clinicians. Even the closest of kin can sometimes be unclear about what their loved ones would desire in critical cases.21
Guiding principles
With insight gained from history of research with human subjects and difficult end-of-life cases, the bioethics movement developed new ways of valuing and examining ethical dilemmas in patient care. A consensus has emerged on a set of guiding principles to assist health care professionals in the wide variety of clinical situations they may encounter. Tom Beauchamp and James Childress advance the clearest interpretation of these principles emerging over time from the common morality of society and the particular context of the clinical environment. These principles are respect for autonomy, nonmaleficence, beneficence, and justice.2
Respect for autonomy refers to the norm of respect for the decision-making capacities of autonomous individuals. Defined as self rule or self governance, autonomy means that competent adults have the fundamental right to determine what happens to their bodies and to make choices in treatment options that are consistent with their own beliefs and values.2 Autonomy is grounded in respect for persons and the inherent dignity and worth of each individual and is reflected in the Code of Ethics of the American Nurses Association.22 In the clinical setting, the autonomy of the patient is often challenged by the vulnerabilities created by pain, sedative effects, and severe illness as well as the anxiety produced by a lack of understanding of the complexities of the modern health care institution, such as the medical language and jargon used by professionals. The obligation of clinical caregivers is to uphold autonomy by engaging in an ongoing process of informed consent, maintaining privacy and confidentiality, and enhancing, to the greatest degree possible, the mental and emotional capacity of the patient for participating in decision making. In the American context, autonomy is often thought of as the first and most important of the four principles.
Nonmaleficence refers to the obligation of clinicians to prevent harm to patients under their care or to minimize risks of harm to the fullest extent possible. This norm is often linked to the medical framework of the Hippocratic admonition primum non nocere, translated to mean “above all, do no harm.”2 The potential for harm to patients in health care can be understood in both broad and narrow terms. Nursing frames this understanding in the ethical obligation to advocate for processes that minimize harm and maximize comfort and support for patients.22 Nonmaleficence refers to the effort made by clinicians to limit physical pain, disability, or even death as a consequence of the treatment process itself. More broadly, the term refers to the duty to alleviate the emotional and spiritual suffering of the patient undergoing the traumatic experience of institutionalization, separation from loved ones, and the inability to make a living among other challenges.
Beneficence is the principle that speaks to the duty of promoting the ultimate welfare of the patient above all other concerns. In common usage, beneficence speaks to acts of mercy, kindness, and charity.2 As such, beneficence and nonmaleficence may be thought of as two sides of the same coin. Nonmaleficence emphasizes not harming the patient in the effort to do good. Beneficence supports doing good for the patient. Again, the obligation to serve as a patient advocate in a manner that promotes health, well being, and especially safety is a component of sound ethical practice for the nursing professional. In health care, beneficence speaks to the humanitarian values that should underlie decision making and treatments offered to vulnerable persons. It is no accident that the word hospital is associated with the term hospitality. Beneficence affirms that patients should be treated as valued guests in what can often be a foreboding institutional environment. It also suggests that, although clinicians often are tempted by interests that conflict with the patient’s welfare, they should seek to set aside those interests or minimize their effects as much as possible in an effort to maintain professional integrity.
The last and perhaps most elusive principle promoted is the principle of justice. The elusiveness of justice is the result of the wide variety of ways it is defined and understood in society. Within the context of health care, justice is best understood as the obligation of clinicians to distribute fairly the medical benefits, risks, and costs associated with the provision of health care.2 As such, persons in similar circumstances are to be treated similarly. The challenges to the fairness principle are immeasurable in the modern American health care system. Global challenges are most visible in the debates concerning universal health insurance, equity of access, and financing the health care industry. Clinical challenges to justice are more evident in the struggle to evenly allocate scarce resources, such as organs for transplant and blood products as well as access to care, services, and beds in emergency and critical care areas. Justice for the practicing nurse might be understood again in terms of advocacy, this time in the promotion of equality in the provision of quality care through the use of appropriate standards of practice for all patients.22
Perianesthesia ethics
Informed consent
Informed consent is the process of communication between a patient and physician that results in the authorization or understanding for a specific medical intervention.23 Informed consent is rooted in respect for persons, patient autonomy, and self determination and formalizes a component of the covenant between the patient and the physician. It is built on the principles of trust and truth telling regarding the use of a particular intervention or treatment to achieve a desired medical outcome.
The nurse might begin by seeking verification of a signed written consent form. Whereas the presence of the form might satisfy the technical act of granting consent, it may or may not fulfill the ethical obligation. Informed consent is more than a means of securing a signature. Rather, it is a process of open two-way communication that implies full disclosure and provides detailed information on the nature of a specific procedure. A comprehensive informed consent process not only reviews the diagnosis and purpose of the intervention but also outlines its potential risks and benefits. It includes alternative treatment options, if any, and the risks and benefits of forgoing the treatment procedure. Informed consent assumes that the threshold elements of patient capacity and voluntary nature are met.24
Informed consent requires that the process be completed by a clinician able to provide the intervention and in a manner that allows time and space for patients to ask questions, seek clarification, and discuss potential options for care. The content of these discussions should be documented and communicated to members of the interdisciplinary team. An adequate informed consent process is further challenged by potential language barriers, such as complex medical terminology, cultural diversity, and functional limitations among populations with cognitive impairments.25,26 All these issues underscore the significance of effective communication in the patient-physician relationship and among members of the interdisciplinary team.
What then is the ethical responsibility of the nurse in the holding area who is faced with the patient’s question of uncertainty and the surgical team’s schedule? To what extent is the nurse’s ethical obligation to serve as a patient advocate in support of an informed decision? How might the nurse’s obligation be affected for the patient who adds the statement, “At least my surgeon promised to be there for the entire operation,” when the nurse knows of that particular surgeon’s tendency toward intermittent presence while residents perform most operations? What if the nurse understood from a colleague that the patient’s original consent was provided under pressure to comply? Specific questions such as these identify just a few of the immediate moral dilemmas that have implications for clinical practice and patient outcomes.
Resuscitation in the perioperative context
By the mid 1990s, a growing dissatisfaction existed with this practice. The evolution of increased respect for patient autonomy evolved from changes in medical practice and the Patient Self-Determination Act of 1990. Complicating matters was a lack of consistency within organizational policies regarding physicians’ obligation to inform patients with existing DNR orders that they would be resuscitated during the perioperative period. Respect for patient autonomy and concern for adequate informed consent procedures challenged old practices and forced the issue onto the agendas of key professional organizations. Emerging from these conversations was support for the practice of required reconsideration. A comprehensive conversation regarding a patient’s DNR status during the administration of anesthesia is recommended between the physician and the patient or surrogate, with the result documented and communicated among health care team members. Required reconsideration has since become the predominant recommended approach supported by the American Society of PeriAnesthesia Nurses, the American College of Surgeons, the American Society of Anesthesiologists, the Association of periOperative RegisteredNurses, and the American Association of Nurse Anesthetists.27–31
Despite the majority movement toward required reconsideration, a lack of consensus remains on the application of this practice among anesthesiologists, nurse anesthetists, and other perianesthesia nurses.32,33 Variation among hospital policies that guide the use of CPR for patients with preexisting DNR orders who undergo surgical intervention and anesthesia reflects this diversity of opinion. Currently, three distinct approaches to addressing this issue dominate the landscape. These approaches include: routine or automatic suspension of DNR orders for a defined time period, required reconsideration of the DNR status with a means approach, and required reconsideration of the DNR status with a goals-oriented approach.
The argument for supporting unrestrained resuscitation is one of clarity for both clinicians and patients or surrogates, but other arguments may also support this position.34 This position reduces the burden on the provider to differentiate whether the underlying cause of a cardiopulmonary arrest is related to the routine effect of anesthesia rather than the result of the patient’s underlying disease process. Unrestrained resuscitation also simplifies the content of conversation between the provider and the patient or surrogate and becomes more a matter of informing the patient or surrogate of hospital policy. Another interpretation is that the practice relieves the patient or surrogate of the burden of a complicated decision in the face of a series of “what if” scenarios that may or may not emerge during surgery.
The minimal ethical obligation in the case of automatic suspension of DNR orders is an intentional and comprehensive conversation between the physician (surgeon or anesthesiologist) and the patient or surrogate before sedation. In the case of automatic suspension of DNR orders, informed consent requires that the physician outlines for the patient the hospital policy, including the duration and context of the suspension. Such clarity minimally offers the patient the opportunity to factor the implications of such a policy into the decision-making process about surgery. Organizational policies that support automatic suspension ideally also incorporate an option for the patient to select another provider, with the recognition that this can have its own complicating factors. In the case of automatic suspension, policies should identify which medical service informs the patient or surrogate. In addition, clear and timely communication should occur with postanesthesia providers regarding the duration of the suspension as the patient progresses through the levels of care from phase I and phase II to extended care.
As previously indicated, patients, surrogates, and clinicians have raised concern regarding the ethical appropriateness of automatic suspensions of DNR orders in the perioperative period, even with the provision of informed discussion. The argument is that such suspension of orders is a violation of a patient’s right to self determination and fails adherence to the principle of patient autonomy.35–44 This position has obvious ethical implications for providers. It requires intentional dialogue with patients or surrogates regarding the options and implications of maintaining or suspending the DNR order during surgery. Organizational policies can mandate such communication and documentation of the conversation, but the ethical challenge to informed consent remains in the details of it. Informed consent in this instance implies that patients or surrogates are offered information about their procedures, including potential risks and benefits, alternative treatment, and the potential implications of foregoing the intervention. Discussion of how resuscitation would be managed in the perioperative period is an essential but complicated discussion. Conversation within this context should be conducted without coercion, in a language that is understandable to patients or surrogates, and with sufficient time to allow questions and concerns to lead to an informed decision.
Clear and consistent communication alone does not readily resolve the complexities of management of a DNR order in the perioperative period.45 Discussion in the literature on the pragmatics of managing the DNR order in the perioperative period is reflected in two approaches, both supporting the ethical obligation to respect patient autonomy. One position suggests a means or procedure-directed approach that examines routine resuscitative actions and determines which interventions would be offered in the perioperative period. The second position supports an ends-oriented approach that examines the goals of the patient relative to the present procedure. Both options suggest a limited resuscitation approach during the perioperative period, as distinct from the two extreme options of suspension of DNR orders with unrestrained resuscitative efforts or maintenance of current DNR orders limiting all interventions not immediately associated with routine anesthesia care.
The procedure-directed approach provides a checklist of specific provider interventions.46 The application of this approach requires consideration of each optional intervention (i.e., those not associated with routine anesthesia care) individually between the patient or surrogate and the surgeon or anesthesia provider.39 The advantages of procedure-directed orders are the reduction of ambiguity and the consistency of application from one clinician to another throughout intraoperative resuscitation management. The limitations to procedure-directed orders include an expectation that anything but the most likely problems would be anticipated in advance and the lack of flexibility offered the clinician in response to a temporary and readily reversible event.
The goal-oriented approach seeks to incorporate the patient’s values as the primary consideration in determination of the extent of resuscitation.47 Patients offer guidance regarding preferred outcomes but leave specific interventions to the discretion of the provider. Although this approach supports patient autonomy, it also provides a larger role for the provider. The advantage to this approach is that it offers flexibility to the clinician to act in accordance with a broad understanding of patient preferences should an unanticipated event occur in the OR setting.46 The limiting argument for this position has been that it risks putting unanticipated decision-making power back in the hands of the physician.
Keys to success for either of these approaches are communication and documentation. The complexity of this issue underscores the significant ethical obligations of the perioperative nurse. The obligation to act in the patient’s best interest demands that the nurse be knowledgeable and informed, beginning with having a clear understanding of the organization’s DNR policy and its specific application to the perianesthesia period.48 Equally important is that the nurse has knowledge of the DNR status of the patient during that period, including any documentation regarding limited resuscitation and knowledge of the timeframe in the case of temporarily suspended DNR orders.
Privacy and confidentiality
Maintaining the privacy and confidentiality of patients remains a challenge for health care organizations and clinicians. Privacy and confidentiality are complementary rather than synonymous concepts.49 Privacy suggests that a patient has the right to control general access and distribution of personal information about one’s health and implies that boundaries that protect a patient’s personal space are respected within a clinical setting. Confidentiality relates to the personal trust that intimate information shared by a patient with a clinician is used only for the patient’s medical benefit. As such, information is shared with those members of the interdisciplinary team on a need-to-know basis. Information should be shared with third parties only with permission of the patient except in the cases of an identified surrogate for the patient who lacks the decision-making capacity. The ethical responsibility to maintain privacy and confidentiality proceeds from the principle of respect for persons that promotes human dignity and maximized patient control.50 Such responsibility is particularly critical for the most vulnerable of patients. This responsibility applies to the preoperative setting when marking surgical sites to ensure minimal exposure. It also applies to treatment of patients under the effects of anesthesia by eliminating and addressing derogatory or disrespectful behaviors or communications.50
Patient safety
The ethical responsibility for all clinicians and health care providers to act in the best interest of patients is no more evident than in the obligation to ensure patient safety. The significance of this obligation on perianesthesia nurses is both organizational and personal. Minimally, this obligation stems from the ethical principle of nonmaleficence. Organizational obligation includes responsibility to ensure that the environment is safe for patients. Critical to patient safety is the requirement that a clinician at any given point in the treatment process has shown appropriate competencies for the level of care being provided. Competency implies possession of the knowledge, skills, attitudes, and behavior to deliver the appropriate level of care on a consistent basis.51 Clinicians are obligated to know and to function within the standard of care of their professional role and the professional standards of practice within their discipline.52 This responsibility can be particularly challenging for nurses in the PACU, an environment frequently characterized by overcrowding because of limited intensive care unit beds and staffing shortages and where nurses might be asked to provide care outside the unit’s scope of care.53
The principle of beneficence speaks to the perianesthesia nurse’s responsibility to a wide range of ethical obligations. Ethical dilemmas faced by clinicians can include how to respond to a colleague who appears impaired in some way, what to do regarding the reporting of a medical error, or how to respond to a situation in which a colleague is engaged in deceptive practice or illegal behavior—all situations that affect maintenance of a safe environment and adherence to ethical practice and organizational guidelines. Responsibility extends to the nurse’s obligation to follow best practice processes and to take initiative to eliminate errors, such as calling “time out” if guidelines such as those designed to ensure correct site surgery are not followed properly.54,55
The hand-off from the OR to the PACU can be complicated by the pressure of time. What essential information needs to be passed from the OR nurse or the nurse anesthetist to the PACU nurse? How should the transfer of a patient whose condition is marginally stable or the one whose condition is hemodynamically stable but in pain be handled between the nurse anesthetist and the PACU nurse? How could this situation be compromised by a demanding OR schedule that anticipates a speedy return to the OR by the anesthetist? Minimal responsibility in this instance includes documentation of the patient’s status on arrival, information on the surgical and anesthesia course, and collaboration in the care of the patient until the PACU nurse accepts responsibilities.56 The assessment and management of pain in the postoperative period remains a critical ethical obligation and can be a source of tension between the transferring anesthesia provider and the receiving PACU nurse. This process can be particularly complicated for the pediatric patient or the geriatric patient with cognitive impairment because clinicians may need knowledge and specialized training for such populations.56 Special care should be taken not to underestimate the level of pain severity and undertreat the patient. The safe transfer of care should be extended again when the patient moves from the PACU to another care setting. Although guidelines for the safe transfer of care have been identified by both the American Society of PeriAnesthesia Nurses and the American Society of Anesthesiologists, successful patient outcomes in these situations are facilitated with clear and proper communication skills.
A corollary of the ethical principle of respect for persons and the obligation to ensure patient safety is truth telling. The ethical responsibility to tell the truth in medicine exists at both organizational and individual patient levels. Organizationally, the perianesthesia nurse needs to determine the ethical course of action in disclosing potential safety problems under the pressure to move patients efficiently through the system. At an individual patient level, the perianesthesia nurse is challenged to determine the ethical course of action in facilitating disclosure of a medical error, even one seemingly inconsequential.57
Resources for resolving ethical dilemmas
Clear and consistent communication between clinicians and patients and among clinicians continues to be the backbone of good ethical practice. Despite the most diligent practice, ethical dilemmas continue to challenge clinicians. The ethical responsibility for the perianesthesia nurse can become particularly burdensome in the perioperative environment, where issues of power and politics are never far away. Identification of resources to support staff seeking resolution of ethical conflicts can relieve the burden. Managers and supervisors should not be overlooked as resources for assistance. Supervisors should be dependable sources for accessing organizational policies or for support in dealing with colleagues in other disciplines. Staff access to organizational and departmental policies has been enhanced with the use of an institution’s Intranet postings. In addition, the code of ethics for nearly all relevant professional nursing organizations is available through Internet web sites. Questions regarding ethical practices related to release of patient information, business practice, or even professional behavior can be referred to ever-expanding corporate compliance programs.
Ethics case review methodology
The struggle around ethical dilemmas for most clinicians occurs when a clinical situation creates a conflict of personal values or when the rights of individual patients appear to not be respected. The use of a pragmatic tool to examine a moral problem is a valuable resource for the novice and the experienced clinician. Thoughtful case analysis requires a reasoned methodology ensuring that a reasoned approach is followed and that influential factors are given appropriate consideration. The use of a case-based methodology can facilitate responsible reflection with an objective theoretic framework while attending to the specifics of a particular situation. Detailed case-based approaches are available.58 In general, the literature points to five common elements for the case review process: assessment and gathering, establishment of ethical questions, identification and analysis of alternatives, selection and implementation, and evaluation.
Identification and analysis of alternatives
Difficult ethical situations are often characterized by more than one morally justifiable course of action. Each alternative should be examined within the context of the medical situation and the patient or surrogate preferences and analyzed with attention to institutional issues and third-party interests. Case history, whether prominent in the literature or particular to the organization, also serves as a resource to assist in the consistent treatment of similar ethical situations.
Summary
Clinical ethics continues to develop into a mature field with established acceptance among health care professionals. Codes of professional ethics are the norm for nursing organizations, and there is a growing literature of ethical issues in perianesthesia nursing. Evolving technology and increased emphasis on patient rights presents ever-increasing options for care and considerations for decision making within the medical community. In addressing these issues, the perianesthesia nursing professional has much to contribute. It is crucial to develop the competencies and skills required to be effective clinicians who possess the critical assessment tools necessary to negotiate difficult situations in an environment of culturally diverse values.
1. American heritage dictionary of the English language, ed 3. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company; 1996.
2. Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of biomedical ethics, ed 6. New York: Oxford University Press; 2008.
3. Fletcher JC, et al. Clinical ethics: history, content, and resources. Fletcher JC, et al. Introduction to clinical ethics, ed 2, Hagerstown, Md: University Publishing Group, 1997.
4. Rothman DJ. Strangers at the bedside: a history of how law and bioethics transformed medical decision making. New York: Basic Books; 1991.
5. Jonsen AR. The birth of bioethics. New York: Oxford University Press; 1998.
6. Alexander L. Medical science under dictatorship. N Engl J Med. 1949;241:39–47.
7. Jones JH. Bad blood. New York: The Free Press; 1993.
8. Heller J. Syphilis victims in U.S. study went untreated for 40 years. NY Times; July 26, 1972.
9. National Research Act of 1974, Pub. L. 93-348.
10. The National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research: The Belmont reportethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research, 1979. available at: http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/policy/belmont.html, March 16, 2011. Accessed on
11. Presidential Memorandum. Review of human subjects protection, released by the White House Office of the Press Secretary; November 24, 2010.
12. In the matter of Karen Quinlan, an alleged incompetent, 70 NJ 10, 355 A.2d 647, 1976.
13. The Multi-Society Task Force on PVS: Medical aspects of the persistent vegetative state—first of two parts. N Engl J Med.1994;330:1499–1508.
14. Cruzan versus Director Missouri Department of Health 497 US 261 11 S. Ct. 2841 1990.
16. Meisel A, et al. Seven legal barriers to end-of-life care: myths, realities, and grains of truth. JAMA.1996;284:2495–2501.
17. Upadya A, et al. Patient, physician, and family member understanding of living wills. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2002;166:1430–1435.
18. Gostin LO. Ethics, the Constitution, and the dying process: the case of Theresa Marie Schiavo. JAMA.2005;293:2403–2407.
19. Wolfson J. Erring on the side of Theresa Schiavo: reflections of the special guardian ad litem. Hastings Center Report.2005;35(3):16–19.
20. Thogmartin JR. Medical examiner, district six of the state of Florida: Report of autopsy for Schiavo, Theresa, case #505439; June 13, 2005.
21. Shalowitz D, et al. The accuracy of surrogate decision makers. Arch Intern Med. 2006;166:493–497.
22. American Nurses Association: Code of ethics for nurses. available at: http://nursingworld.org/MainMenuCategories/EthicsStandards/CodeofEthicsforNurses.aspx, March 17, 2011. Accessed
23. American Medical Association: Informed consent. available at: http://www.ama-assn.org/ama/pub/physician-resources/medical-ethics/about-ethics-group/ethics-resource-center/educational-resources/federation-repository-ethics-documents-online/american-college-physicians/acp-physician-and-patient.page, January 2, 2012. Accessed
24. Boyle RS. The process of informed consent. Fletcher JS, et al. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics, ed 3, Hagerstown, Md: University Publishing Group, 2005.
25. Galanti GA. Applying cultural competence to perianesthesia nursing. J Perianesth Nurs. 2006;21(2):97–102.
26. Sullivan EE. Issues of informed consent in the geriatric population. J Perianesth Nurs. 2004;19(6):430–432.
27. American Association of Perianesthesia Nurses: A position statement on the perianesthesia patient with a do-not-resuscitate advance directive. available at: http://www.aspan.org/Portals/6/docs/ClinicalPractice/PositionStatement/1012/Pos_Stmt_1_DNR.pdf, March 16, 2011. Accessed
28. American College of Surgeons: [ST-19] Statement on advance directives by patients: “Do not resuscitate” in the operating room. available at: http://www.facs.org/fellows_info/statements/st-19.html, January 2, 2012. Accessed
29. American Society of Anesthesiologists: Standards, guidelines, statements and other documents. available at: http://www.asahq.org/For-Members/Clinical-Information/Standards-Guidelines-and-Statements.aspx, March 17, 2011. Accessed
30. Association of Operating Room Nurses: AORN Position Statement on Perioperative Care of Patients with Do-Not-Resuscitate or Allow-Natural-Death Orders. available at: http://www.aorn.org/PracticeResources/AORNPositionStatements/Position_DoNotResuscitate/, March 17, 2011. Accessed
31. American Association of Nurse Anesthetists: AANA Position Statements, Advisory Opinions, and Considerations. available at: http://www.aana.com/Resources.aspx?id=24804, March 17, 2011. Accessed
32. Fallat ME, Deshpande JK. and the Section on Surgery, Section on Anesthesia and Pain Medicine, and Committee on Bioethics, American Academy of Pediatrics: Do-not-resuscitate orders for the pediatric patients who require anesthesia and surgery. Pediatrics.2004;114(6):1686–1692.
33. Stack CG, Perring J. Pediatric DNAR orders in the perioperative period. Pediatric Anesthesia. 2009;19:964–971.
34. Mohr M. Ethical conflicts during anesthesia “Do not resuscitate” orders in the operating room. Anesthetist. 1997;46(4):267–274.
35. Walker RM. DNR in the OR resuscitation as an operative risk. JAMA. 1991;266(17):2407–2412.
36. Cohen CB, Cohen PJ, Required reconsideration of “do not resuscitate” orders in the operating room and certain other treatment settings. Law Med Health Care.1992;20(4):354–363.
37. Igoe S, et al. Ethics in the OR: DNR and patient autonomy. Nurs Manage.1993;24(9):112A,D,H.
38. Golanowski M. Do-not-resuscitate: informed consent in the operating room and post anesthesia care unit. J Post Anesth Nurs.1995;10(1):9–11.
39. Craig DB. Do not resuscitate orders in the operating room. Can J Anaesth. 1996;43(8):840–851.
40. Lonchyna VA. To resuscitate or not . . . in the operating room: the need for hospital policies for surgeons regarding DNR orders. Ann Health Law.1997;6:209–227.
41. Goldberg S. Do-not-resuscitate orders in the OR—suspend or enforce. AORN J. 2002;75(2):296–299.
42. Saver C. Knowing when to stop: DNR in the OR. OR Manager.2007;23(11):17–21.
43. Berlandi JL, Duncan J. Perioperative DNR orders, palliative surgery, and ethics. Perioperative Nursing Clinics. 2008;3(3):223–232.
44. Ball KA. Do-not-resuscitate. Orders in surgery: decreasing the confusion. AORN J.2009;89(1):140–146.
45. Ewanchuk M, Brindley PG. Perioperative do not resuscitate orders—doing ‘nothing’ when ‘something’ can be done. Crit Care. 2006;10(4):219.
46. Guarisco KK. Managing do not resuscitate orders in the perianesthesia period. J Perianesth Nurs. 2004;19(5):300–307.
47. Truog RD, et al. DNR in the OR: a goal-directed approach. Anesthesiology.1999;90(1):281–295.
48. Keffer MJ, Keffer HL. The do-not-resuscitate order: moral responsibilities of the perioperative nurse. AORN J.1994;59(3):648–650.
49. DeRenzo EG. Privacy and confidentiality. Fletcher JS, et al. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics, ed 3, Hagerstown, Md: University Publishing Group, 2005.
50. Baillie L, Ilott L. Promoting the dignity of patients in perioperative practice. J Perioper Prac. 2010;20(8):278–282.
51. Burden N, Saufl N. Why ethical standards? An introduction to the Perianesthesia standards for ethical practice. J Perianesth Nurs. 2001;16(1):2–5.
52. Mamaril ME. Standards of perianesthesia nursing practice: advocating patient safety. J Perianesth Nurs.2003;18(3):168–172.
53. Iacono MV. Perianesthesia staffing . . . thinking beyond numbers. J Perianesth Nurs. 2006;21(5):346–352.
54. Odom-Forren J. A tragedy unfolds: lessons to learn. J Perianesth Nurs.2006;21(5):367–369.
55. American Association of Perianesthesia Nurses: A position statement on perianesthesia safety. available at: http://www.aspan.org/Portals/6/docs/ClinicalPractice/PositionStatement/1012/Pos_Stmt_10_Perianes_Safety.pdf, August 5, 2011. Accessed
56. Schroeter K. Pain management: ethical issues for the perianesthesia nurse. J Perianesth Nurs.1999;14(6):393–397.
57. Espin S, et al. Error or “act of God”? A study of patients’ and operating room team members’ perceptions of error definition, reporting, and disclosure. Surgery. 2006;139:6–14.
58. EM Spencer. A case method for consideration of moral problems. Fletcher JS, et al. Fletcher’s introduction to clinical ethics, ed 3, Hagerstown, Md: University Publishing Group, 2005.