CHAPTER 28 Ethical Issues in Developmental-Behavioral Pediatrics: A Historical Approach
Ethical issues in developmental-behavioral pediatrics (DBP) fall within the larger discipline of bioethics. Children with developmental or behavioral disorders may have unique needs or face end-of-life issues more frequently than do other children, but the fundamental approach to resolving ethical issues is and should be the same as for any other child. Philosophers have sought to ground clinical ethical decisions in theories of morality; in everyday practice, clinicians and families work together to determine the best interests of a particular child within the constraints of law and generally accepted social values. Consensus on ethical decisions has varied with time and place, as each community has struggled to define its core values in laws, words, and deeds. This is especially true with regard to ethical issues and persons with developmental disabilities, because the way clinicians understand and value the quality of life of people with disabilities has changed dramatically since the 1950s. The role of history is therefore critical in understanding ethical issues in DBP.
OVERVIEW OF TRADITIONAL BIOETHICS
Professional Codes of Conduct
Guidelines for the professional behavior of medical practitioners have been promulgated for at least 4000 years, according to writings from ancient Egypt and Mesopotamia. The comparatively recent Oath attributed to Hippocrates (460-380 b.c.) is among the most famous, but other prominent medical writers such as Galen and Maimonides offered advice on privacy, duty to patients, and end-of-life issues.1 Such guidelines express values common to medical practitioners, but they also serve to elevate the standing of medicine as a profession and not a mere vocation. For example, the American Medical Association was founded in 1847 in part to restrain unseemly competition among medical practitioners; that same year, the association’s leadership disseminated a code of appropriate behavior for medical practitioners that included rules for referrals and fee splitting.2
Since the early 1980s, a surge of interest in professional behavior has led a number of organizations to develop codes of conduct for health care providers (Table 28-1). The European Federation of Internal Medicine, the American College of Physicians–American Society of Internal Medicine, and American Board of Internal Medicine, for example, collaborated to publish a physician charter outlining principles to which “all medical professionals can and should aspire.”3 As in similar documents since the 1950s, the physician charter focused on principles that many argue provide the foundation for medical practice: beneficence, autonomy, privacy, and social justice or equity. Rules of professional behavior described in these or similar principles are now being integrated more fully into the training and accreditation of physicians; examples include recommendations and requirements of the Accreditation Council for Graduate Medical Education, the Association of American Medical Colleges, and the National Board of Medical Examiners.4
TABLE 28-1 Professionalism According to Medical Institutions4
Institution | Publication | Definition |
---|---|---|
ABIM, ACP-ASIM, EFIM | A Physician Charter (2002)3 | Professionalism: a foundation of the social contract for medicine |
Principles: primacy of patient welfare, patient autonomy, social justice | ||
Commitments: | ||
Professional competence | ||
Scientific knowledge | ||
Professional responsibilities | ||
Managing conflicts of interest | ||
Patient confidentiality | ||
Honesty with patients | ||
Improving quality of care | ||
Improving access to care | ||
Appropriate relationships | ||
Just distributions of finite resources | ||
General Medical Council | Good Medical Practice54 | Make the care of your patient your first concern |
Treat every patient politely and considerately | ||
Respect patient’s dignity and privacy | ||
Listen to patients and respect their views | ||
Give patients information in a way they can understand | ||
Respect the right of patients to be fully involved in decisions | ||
Keep your professional knowledge and skills up to date; recognize the limits of your competence | ||
Be honest and trustworthy | ||
Respect and protect confidential information | ||
Make sure that your personal beliefs do not prejudice your patients’ care | ||
Act quickly to protect patients from risk (from unfit physicians) | ||
Avoid abusing your position as a physician | ||
Work with colleagues in the ways that best serve patients’ interests | ||
AAMC | Medical School Objectives (1999)55 | Knowledgeable: scientific method, biomedicine |
Skillful: clinical skills, reasoning, condition managing, communication | ||
Altruistic: respect, compassion, ethical probity, honesty, avoidance of conflicts of interest | ||
Dutiful: population health, advocacy, and outreach to improve nonbiological determinants of health, prevention, information management, health systems management |
AAMC, American Association of Medical Colleges; ABIM, American Board of Internal Medicine; ACP-ASIM, American College of Physicians–American Society of Internal Medicine; EFIM, European Federation of Internal Medicine.
The seemingly universal nature of ethical principles is underlined by their international scope. The Declaration of Geneva adopted in 1948 by the World Medical Association was an attempt to describe a world standard for medical professionals, and there is evidence that the professionals’ beneficial influence extended beyond the physician-patient relationship to help shape humanistic and egalitarian features of the world’s legal and political institutions.5 Indeed, the United Nations General Conference began devising universal standards in the field of bioethics that extended far beyond professional conduct by physicians. The 2005 Universal Draft Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights outlines the ethical practices expected of policymakers, health care providers, and professional groups (Table 28-2).6
TABLE 28-2 Universal Draft Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights6,48
Concept | Definition |
---|---|
Human dignity and human rights | Recognition that all persons have unconditional worth |
Equality, equity and justice | Equality: equal treatment of individuals in a similar situation |
Equity: the use of discretion when examining special circumstances of particular cases; a correct mechanism to formal equality | |
Justice: normative principle describing, how institutions, society, and other groups of people should act; implementing the balance between equality and equity | |
Benefit and harm | Any decision or practice shall seek to benefit the person concerned and to minimize the possible harm |
Respect for cultural diversity and pluralism | Ethical standards must be interpreted and adapted to the manifold ways in which cultures of different social groups and societies find expression |
Nondiscrimination and nonstigmatization | Nondiscrimination: prohibition of discrimination, which is treating a morally neutral and immutable characteristic as having a negative effect |
Nonstigmatization: elimination of stigma requires a longer process of social transformation in which ethics and ethics teaching can play a significant role | |
Autonomy and individual responsibility | Individuals cannot be instrumentalized and treated merely as a means to a scientific end; they should be granted the authority to make autonomous decisions in all aspects of their lives |
Informed consent | A patient or potential research subject has to receive relevant, structured, and individually tailored information that makes it possible for him or her to make a decision whether or not to accept medical treatment, as well as to understand and cope with the diagnosis; also, special protection shall be given to persons who do not have the capacity to consent |
Privacy and confidentiality | Privacy: guarantees a control over personal information |
Confidentiality: refers to the relationship between doctor and patient (or researcher and research subject); it provides that the shared information shall remain secret, confidential, and not disclosed to third person (unless strictly defined interest justifies disclosure under domestic law) | |
Solidarity and cooperation | Collective social protection and fair opportunity in access to health care worldwide, with special attention to vulnerable groups |
Social responsibility | Takes into account the wider social dimension of the scientific process by specifying five elements of universal priority (access to quality health care, access to adequate nutrition and water, improvement of living conditions and the environment, elimination of marginalization and exclusions of persons on the basis of any ground, and reduction of poverty and illiteracy) |
Sharing of benefits | Benefits from advances in biology, genetics, and medicine shall be made available to all |
Responsibility for the biosphere | Recognizes that human beings are an integral part of the biosphere and have responsibilities toward other forms of life and future generations |
Moral Theory
For centuries, many physicians have grounded ethical behavioral in their religious beliefs, whether invoking the gods of Hippocrates’s Greece or the monotheism of today. Particularly in the United States, appeals to the Ten Commandments or especially the “golden rule”—“Do unto others as you would have them do unto you”—are especially common approaches to proscribing behavior. Other physicians and scholars have turned to secular theories of moral behavior. John Stuart Mill’s and Jeremy Bentham’s utilitarianism, commonly understood as the “greatest good for the greatest number,” is one system that focuses on the consequences of given actions as the tool for making the best choice. Immanuel Kant held that moral behavior would follow from meeting the rational requirement to choose the course of action that a person would want everyone in a similar position to follow, as if that person were setting the rules for behavior. In the 1970s, largely in response to reports of abuse of research subjects in the Tuskegee syphilis experiments, the U.S. federal government commissioned a group of scholars to provide a guide for the proper conduct of research, and the resulting Belmont Report focused on the principles of autonomy, beneficence, and justice. Further developed by Beauchamp and Childress, “principlism” has been widely applied to clinical ethics as well.7
Gert argued that these traditional systems of moral theory are generally not useful in resolving clinical and other ethics debates.8 Each of these systems has noteworthy exceptions, and any system that sometimes produces the wrong answer cannot be relied upon to produce the right answer when faced with an ethical dilemma. Furthermore, Gert argued, moral theories that suggest that there is one right answer can actually impede resolution of ethical dilemmas by creating conflict among participants. Instead, according to Gert, most dilemmas can be resolved if there can be agreement on the facts, and in cases of true conflict on values, such as abortion, there can be more than one morally acceptable answer. He offered his own approach of moral rules and ideals and suggested that breaking the rules is appropriate when a person would be willing to describe publicly why he or she is breaking a rule and have it stand as policy. For example, breaking a promise of confidentiality is appropriate when a clinician learns that a patient plans to injure somebody.
Autonomy, Beneficence, and Justice
Despite the limits of principlism for resolving ethical dilemmas, it provides a useful framework for understanding clinical ethics.9
There are three basic elements to autonomy: agency (awareness of oneself, desires, and intentions), independence (absence of influences), and rationality (capacity for reflection on desires). Respect for a patient’s autonomy is the fundamental principle underlying privacy, confidentiality, valid consent, and refusal of treatment. In the United States, the right to privacy was first recognized as protected by the Constitution in the 1965 U.S. Supreme Court ruling, Griswold v. Connecticut,9a a case involving use of contraception by married couples. In clinical practice, autonomy has come to mean that patients generally decide what medical care they receive, and their wish to refuse treatment should be respected if they are fully informed and appreciate the consequences of their refusal. Because of age and cognitive level, children are typically not deemed competent to make medical decisions. Parents or guardians are usually called upon to do what is in the best interests of the child. As children enter their teens, they begin to participate in health care decisions, especially when the issues involve pregnancy or treatment for sexually transmitted infections.
In attempting to follow the principles of autonomy and beneficence, the health care provider will confront inequities in the social and economic fabric of society. The philosopher John Rawls offered one way to describe such inequities: The “natural lottery” distributes properties through birth, and the “social lottery” distributes social assets through family property, social class, and education. The principle of justice holds that people do not deserve advantageous properties any more than they deserve disadvantageous properties.7 In the United States, however, children living in poverty and those without health insurance are much more likely to experience poor heath than are those who are wealthier and those with health insurance. A just distribution of resources implies that all children, indeed all persons, should have equal access to medical treatment and adequate education, housing, and nutrition. Children with special health care needs are especially likely to suffer from inadequate access to beneficial medical care, and their families face substantial economic hardship.
Principlism, Historical Context, and the Role of the Bioethics Committee
Despite the popularity of principlism as a framework for clinical ethics, there is empirical evidence that education in such principles of ethics does not affect moral decision making as much as do culture, personal history, and social and institutional context.10 Indeed, it is sometimes difficult in practice to balance all the principles equally and simultaneously, inasmuch as an emphasis on one principle often minimizes that on another. For example, in an effort to minimize harm to a patient with an aggressive medical intervention, the physician might indirectly diminish the patient’s autonomy. Beneficence and autonomy often conflict with the principle of social justice, in the presence of finite resources in health care. An individual physician may advocate for a third liver transplantation for her patient, for example, but in the context of a long waiting list, social justice suggests that other patients should have an opportunity to benefit from that limited resource. Which principle takes precedence? Who is to decide which principle is most important in a given case?
The answers to these questions vary with time and place. Each society works out an approximate consensus for most ethical issues, and this consensus may shift over time. For example, during the 1950s in the United States, there was a general consensus that beneficence trumped autonomy: the physician knew best what to do at the end of life, and it was appropriate to withhold information from patients and families. Through the 1960s and 1970s, such “paternalism” came under attack as part of a larger movement questioning the beneficence of institutional authority, and today autonomy typically outweighs beneficence (see Chapter 8B).11 This shift towards patient autonomy is embodied in the case of Nancy Cruzan* in 1990, when the U.S. Supreme Court recognized the right of competent persons to decline medical treatment even if it led to the person’s death. Living wills and advanced directives now instruct the health care team to respect the wishes of the patient at the end of life.
One way of defining the social consensus on controversial ethical issues is through institutional bioethics committees. Since the 1970s, such committees have been increasingly active in the United States and elsewhere, in part to fulfill the requirement by the Joint Commission on Accreditation of Healthcare Organizations that hospitals have a mechanism for addressing ethical issues in patient care. One key role of an institutional bioethics committee is to define current standards of ethical practice: that is, to help the entire community understand what the social consensus is with regard to typical issues such as confidentiality and end-of-life decisions. The membership of a bioethics committee is therefore crucial for its success: Some members should be well trained in the philosophical principles of bioethics, some should be legal experts, some should have experience with pastoral care, some should have clinical experience with common ethical issues, and some, arguably, should have a personal experience of living with a disability.12 Overall diversity of membership is crucial, however, because the committee needs to be able to say that its deliberations reflect the broad consensus of a community. In this case, diversity refers to gender, age, disability, race/ethnicity, professional background, political viewpoints, and association with the hospital. The presence of at least one committee person with a developmental disability helps ensure that special issues related to persons with disabilities are appropriately considered. Table 28-3 describes the properties of an institutional ethics committee according to the United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (UNESCO), the American Medical Association, and the American Academy of Pediatrics.
TABLE 28-3 Guidelines for Institutional Ethics Committees (IECs)
Organization | Publication | Definition |
---|---|---|
UNESCO | Universal Draft Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights6,46 |
Necessity: independent, multidisciplinary, and pluralist ethics should be established, promoted, and supported at the appropriate level
|
AAP, American Academy of Pediatrics; AMA, American Medical Association; CEJA, (AMA) Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs; UNESCO, United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization.
END-OF-LIFE DECISIONS AND THE HISTORY OF PERSONS WITH DEVELOPMENTAL DISABILITIES
End-of-life decisions constitute a critical area of bioethics and, for the purposes of this chapter, also provide a salient example of how the history of persons with developmental disabilities informs current ethical issues. Centuries of discrimination against persons with developmental disabilities, sterilization and euthanasia early in the 20th century, and the disability rights movement of the late 20th century are a few of the key points in this history. This brief historical overview is necessarily an oversimplification, and emerging evidence suggests that life for persons with disabilities before the modern period in particular was much more nuanced than previously acknowledged.13 To understand how current ethical debates are informed by a popular understanding of history, however, this section focuses on major points in Western civilization that provide the context for ethical issues such as death and dying.
From Antiquity to the Enlightenment
Persons with disabilities have suffered from discrimination and abuse since antiquity, although such treatment was not universal. In ancient Greece and Rome, for example, most scholars attributed disabling condition to failure of parents to properly revere the gods. Hippocrates’ hypothesis that epilepsy was a disturbance of the natural processes in the mind was a rare example of seeking material causes of disease. In their everyday lives, many persons with disabilities served as scapegoats for minor or major problems, and they typically pursued the only work available: as singers, dancers, musicians, jugglers, or clowns. Blind people were occasionally revered as poets and bards, but that was an exception to typical beliefs about the cognitive abilities of persons with disabilities. Deaf people, according to Aristotle, were incapable of learning. However, Aristotle also echoed Socrates in his admonition to “pity the weak,” and thus the city of Athens provided some support to individuals with disabilities. In the warlike state of Sparta, in contrast, “deformed” and sickly infants were sometimes abandoned, because their continued existence threatened the strength of the state.
During the Middle Ages, civil authority was deeply intertwined with the Christian religious hierarchy throughout Europe, which affected the civil rights of persons with disabilities. In early modern England, “poor laws” provided some material support to individuals unable to work because of a disability. In other places, however, the negative view of persons with disabilities meant that they were not allowed to inherit property; testify in court; or make a deed, contract, or will. Even worse, in 1484 Pope Innocent VIII proclaimed a war against witches, and during the next 300 years, there were more than 100,000 witch trials throughout Europe. People with disabilities were frequently accused of demonic possession, and tens of thousands were tortured, hanged, or burned at the stake.
Similar to the teaching of prominent Jewish scholars, the Islamic tradition typically highlighted the sacredness of all human life.9 Although the study of disability in the medieval Islamic world is only in its infancy, preliminary evidence suggests that Islamic society generally did not associate disabilities with moral or spiritual deficiencies.14 However, the legal rights of persons considered to be incompetent were considerably curtailed, and they were typically entrusted to a legal guardian’s care. Medical treatment for this population varied, including incantations, magic, exorcisms, and a physiological approach adopted from Galen: Like the famous physician, Islamic practitioners hoped to heal cognitive or physical disabilities by restoring the balance of humors.
Persons with disabilities benefited from these broader changes in society. Among richer families, for example, deaf first-born sons were taught to read and write in order to fulfill legal inheritance requirements. In Germany and France in particular, individuals with disabilities began to take part in community activities, and the discipline of physical therapy emerged to treat persons with physical disabilities. The most dramatic development was that governments in Europe and the United States built large hospitals to treat mental retardation in the early 1800s. Founders of these institutions believed that special training programs and the appropriate environment could cure mental retardation. Optimism waned in the late 1800s, however, because discharges were rare and doctors began to recognize mental retardation as a chronic problem. Underfunded and overwhelmed, these institutions became custodial care centers, and reports of horrific conditions recurred throughout the 20th century.15
Twentieth Century and Eugenics
Pernick used this example to remind us that ethical issues regarding withholding of treatment from persons with disabilities are not the result of technological advances in the 20th century.16 Decisions about what care to provide to persons with disabilities have a certain continuity throughout human history. Ancient Spartans believed that infants who survived exposure were fit to live; medieval Christians attempted religious cures of persons with mental retardation; early modern physicians hoped that by bleeding patients, they could restore humoral balance and thus health; Enlightenment scholars believed that properly constructed institutions could dispel mental afflictions. Although modern medicine may judge such practices as ineffective or barbaric, practitioners (and patients) understood them to be the standard of care, and hence decisions to apply or withhold them share common themes with such debates today.
As Pernick also pointed out, the specific historical context is critical for understanding how such ethical debates are resolved. Haiselden’s actions took place at a time in American history, for example, when eugenics was an accepted social philosophy among many mainstream scholars, such as Judge Oliver Wendell Holmes, geneticist Charles Davenport, and other leaders across the political spectrum. By combining Darwin’s theory of evolution with an emerging understanding of genetics, advocates of eugenics believed that they could eliminate pain from disease and inequity in U.S. society in a single generation. They understood human behavior in simple genetic terms: Characteristics such as intelligence, honesty, and sobriety were passed on according to mendelian genetics. The future therefore lay in encouraging “fit” couples to marry and discouraging others from parenthood. Mental retardation in particular was seen as an inherited condition that at best did not contribute to society and too often led to crime and general depravity. Advocates of eugenics believed that persons with mental retardation could not be trusted to refrain voluntarily from procreation; they persuaded many states to pass laws that led to the involuntary sterilization of adults with mental retardation. Upheld by the U.S. Supreme Court in their 1927 Buck v. Bell16a decision, such laws resulted in the sterilization of more than 60,000 individuals. In Nazi Germany, more than 200,000 individuals with disabilities were euthanized in that nation’s atrocious effort to eliminate disability.
The Disability Rights Movement
Despite the work of such advocacy groups, however, most disabled people remained hidden from public view, either in their homes or in institutions. Well into the 20th century, American society still treated its disabled population, especially those with mental disabilities, as a group that needed to be controlled by segregation, sterilization, and isolation. In the1950s more than 500,000 Americans were housed in overcrowded psychiatric hospitals with custodial care.17 Mental retardation, like many chronic conditions, was associated with poverty, immorality, and racial or ethnic minority status.
Public perception of developmental disabilities changed also because of the efforts of famous families who began to publicly discuss their experience of disability. Before the 1960s, most families hid any association with disability, and even today many people vaguely remember hearing about or visiting a family member who lived in an institution. President Franklin Roosevelt contracted polio long before he was president, for example, but in his years in office from 1932 until his death in 1945, not a single picture that revealed his disability was ever printed. An unspoken code of honor in the White House and among press photographers allowed the general public to believe that Roosevelt had fully recovered from polio. Roosevelt and his colleagues assumed that the American public could not accept a president with a disability.18
By the time that John F. Kennedy became president in 1960, the American people were ready to openly discuss disability. Largely through the urging of his sister Eunice, President Kennedy revealed that he had a sister Rose with mental retardation and argued that the nation had a responsibility to do more for persons with disabilities. Kennedy was following the example of other public figures such as author Pearl S. Buck* and entertainer Roy Rogers,† whose personal stories helped many families overcome the shame commonly associated with mental retardation. As president, Kennedy had the ability to make an enormous difference. His expert President’s Panel on Mental Retardation recommended investing in prevention, basic research, and training professionals to provide health and special education to persons with mental retardation and other developmental disabilities. Through legislation and federal directives, millions of federal dollars were allocated to support maternal and child health programs, train teachers and physicians, and investigate the causes of mental retardation (see Chapter 8A).19 Today more than $40 billion per year in federal and state spending is devoted to education, health care, and other programs for persons with developmental disabilities. Nearly all large state institutions for persons with mental retardation/developmental disabilities have closed, and interdisciplinary outpatient care has been the recognized standard since the 1950s.
Despite such federal programs, however, most persons with developmental disabilities still faced many barriers to full participation in school, work, and community activities. In the 1970s, disability rights advocates used legislation, court rulings, and public acts of disobedience to claim full access to all aspects of American life. Ed Roberts* and Judy Heumann,† for example, each completed university degrees and joined the workforce despite prejudice and administrative roadblocks that prevented persons with disabilities from participating in public schools and the workplace. These two renowned leaders of the disability rights movement eventually held government posts designed to remove barriers to education and employment, thus helping to reform the very institutions that once tried to exclude them. Access to a “free appropriate public education” was ensured legally to all children with disabilities in 1975 when Congress passed Public Law 94-142 (Education of All Handicapped Children Act), now codified as the Individuals with Disabilities Education Act.20
More general access to public institutions was ensured in the aftermath of a critical incident in 1977, when disability rights activists in nine cities staged demonstrations and occupied the offices of the federal Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. They also conducted a “sit-in” to force the President Carter’s administration to enact Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act of 1973, which made it illegal for any federal agency, public university, federal contractor, or any other federally funded institutions to discriminate on the basis of a disability. The demonstrations galvanized the disability community nationwide, particularly in San Francisco, where protests lasted for nearly a month. The legal protections of Section 504 were extended beyond federal institutions with the passing of Developmental Disabilities Act in 1990, and subsequent court decisions have affirmed that persons with disabilities must have the opportunity to participate fully in the community (Table 28-4).
TABLE 28-4 Key Disability Rights Laws in the United States in the Late 20th Century49–51
Law | Summary |
---|---|
The Rehabilitation Act of 1973 (Public Law 93-112) |
Disability culture has important implications for health care. Traditionally, disabled people were viewed by medical professionals through the prism of a “medical model of disability.” Disabled people “suffered” from a reduced quality of life as a result of their impairments, which were medical problems that needed to be cured or obviated through medical interventions. The social model of disability challenges these assumptions by suggesting that there is nothing intrinsically “wrong” with a person with a disability. Rather, disability occurs as a natural part of life. The challenges and stigma confronting people with disabilities in society are the result of physical and social barriers and prejudices that exist in society. Thus, decisions about the medical treatment of people with disabilities should be grounded in an underlying assumption that a disabled life has inherent value and dignity and need not be unduly medicalized and cured. Just as most people of color living in a predominately white society do not yearn to be white, people with disabilities do not seek to be “cured” of their disability.21
Implications of the Disability Rights Movement for End-of-Life Decisions
In the early 1900s, the physician typically made nearly all end-of-life decisions. During the Bollinger case, for example, surveys demonstrated that only a minority of people favored allowing parents any say in the decision-making process. For most of the 20th century, the central role of the physician remained intact. As late as the 1970s, physicians routinely withheld necessary surgery from children with disabilities such as Down syndrome or spina bifida. At one prominent university’s intensive care nursery in 1973, for example, 43 of the 299 consecutive deaths resulted from the health care team’s decision to withhold treatment because of the infants’ extremely poor prognosis for a “meaningful life.”22 As noted previously, able-bodied persons must be cautious when making judgments about quality of life for a person with a disability. Health care providers in particular prize superior cognitive ability and full control over all aspects of their lives, making it difficult for them to imagine the worth of a life with a cognitive or physical impairment.23,24
Through the 1970s and 1980s, physicians in the United States gradually moved away from taking primary responsibility for end-of-life decisions and began to involve patients and families. Autonomy in end-of-life decisions is now commonly granted to competent adults in North America, and most scholars of pediatric ethics believe that families should play a critical role in end-of-life decisions for children.25 The American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics, for example, endorsed “individualized decision making about life-sustaining medical treatment” and argued “these decisions should be jointly made by physicians and parents.”26 According to one formulation of the best-interest model of decision making, reasonable and informed people committed to the well-being of the child should consider the immediate and long-term interests of the child and then seek to maximize benefits and minimize burdens.27
Withholding medical treatment for infants younger than 1 year is more complicated because of the so-called Baby Doe regulations. In 1981 the parents of a newborn with Down syndrome and tracheoesophageal fistula refused to consent to a standard operation that would have enabled the child to take food and water by mouth. President Reagan, his Surgeon General C. Everett Koop, and other leaders of the right-to-life movement joined forces with disability rights leaders who feared that babies with disabilities were not getting appropriate treatment because of discrimination. The Child Abuse Amendments of 1984 defines one form of child abuse as the “withholding of medically indicated treatment” from children, and the statute recognizes only three conditions in which life-sustaining treatment is optional: when a baby is comatose, when treatment would merely prolong dying rather than correct the infant’s life-threatening conditions, and when the provision of such a treatment would be futile and inhumane. Many neonatologists have interpreted these rules as forcing them to continue aggressive treatment of such newborns, although the American Academy of Pediatrics’ guidelines suggest that the rules provide more discretion than is commonly assumed.26 Although debate has persisted since the Baby Doe rules were effected, the general consensus among ethicists and state governments seems to be that all children, regardless of age, deserve the flexibility of individualized judgments through a best-interest model.28
As demonstrated by the case of Terri Schiavo,* however, there remains a strong current in American political and moral life that holds that life is worth preserving at all costs.29 The dramatic showdown between the parents and spouse of Ms. Schiavo, a young woman in a permanent vegetative state, provoked responses from all levels of government and public life in the United States. Many medical ethicists viewed this case as reopening issues that seemed settled with the Cruzan case in 1990, and yet a variety of politicians, religious leaders, and disability rights advocates battled to preserve Ms. Schiavo’s life despite testimony by expert witnesses and a multitude of court decisions. Those who believe that any life—even one of pain and suffering—is better than death typically reject withholding or withdrawing care at the end of life.
The history of persons with disabilities helps explain why many disability rights advocates are extremely cautious in debates about end-of-life decisions, including euthanasia and physician-assisted suicide. Even a charitable interpretation of disability history cannot ignore the forced sterilization of adults with mental retardation in the United States and the euthanasia in Nazi Germany. Daily experience of discrimination adds to this understanding of disability history, and examples of more recent court decisions that undervalue a life with a disability are not hard to find.30
Although the older and more recent history of persons with disabilities provides reason for caution on end-of-life issues, a core principle of the disability rights movement—respect for self-determination—is that persons with disabilities should have the same rights as any able-bodied person to avoid pain and burdensome care. Scholars such as Beltran and Nelson31 have argued that respect for persons with disabilities does not necessarily mean that life must be preserved at all costs. What it does suggest is that decisions should be based on the best interests of that particular individual, without preconceived notions about the quality of life with a disability. Thus, for example, if a child with Down syndrome has leukemia and has experienced relapse despite aggressive treatment, decisions about further intervention should be based on that particular child’s quality of life, just as they would for any child with a similar prognosis. Similarly, medical interventions such as feeding tubes or antibiotics for pneumonia should be based on whether such interventions allow that child to continue participating in life activities that are meaningful to the particular family and child.
GENETICS, SURGICAL SHAPING, AND ASSUMPTIONS ABOUT DISABILITY
Surgical Shaping
Innovative surgical procedures hold promise to reduce impairment or at least the appearance of a disability. Although surgical repair of a cleft lip or cleft palate has long been well accepted, controversy surrounds procedures such as cochlear implants for profound hearing impairment, facial reconstruction for children with Down syndrome, and limb-lengthening for little people (defined as a person with a medical or genetic condition that usually results in an adult height of 4 feet 10 inches [147 cm] or shorter). Cochlear implants are routinely performed in major medical centers, although some advocates of deaf culture continue to argue that such surgery is serving to eliminate a linguistic minority.32 Surgery to repair a cleft lip is standard of care for functional and aesthetic reasons, but reconstructing the face of a child with Down syndrome is highly controversial because it suggests that there is something inherently wrong with having certain facial features. Limb-lengthening procedures are fraught with complications; most little people function well with assistive technology and environmental modifications.
There are obviously differences among these procedures. Limb-lengthening seems to have some functional significance, whereas facial surgery for children with Down syndrome seems purely cosmetic. There is evidence that some children with cochlear implants learn to hear and speak better than do hearing-impaired children who focus solely on sign language, although on average neither group of hearing-impaired children learn as well as their non–hearing-impaired peers. Cochlear implants also carry certain risks such as meningitis.33 Despite these differences in functional significance, there is also a critical similarity among these sorts of procedures. They do not save or prolong life, and there is relatively little evidence that they improve function more than do less invasive approaches. Indeed, they are typically offered to parents with the goal of making the child appear less different, in hopes of reducing the societal stigma or environmental inconveniences associated with having a disability. Thus, a child is subjected to a surgical procedure in many cases simply because some adults are uncomfortable with the child’s appearance. Such motivation conflicts with a basic tenet of the disability rights movement by suggesting that there is something inherently wrong with the disabled child that must be fixed.34
The history of early surgery to augment gender assignment in children with ambiguous genitalia provides a cautionary example.35,36 On the basis almost exclusively of the work of John Money, gender identity was thought to be malleable before age 2 years, and surgery was thus indicated to assign gender on the basis of appearance and chances for procreation. Since the 1980s, Money’s thesis has been attacked—most famously, by the key patient who served to buttress his theory. Some evidence suggests that adults who were surgically assigned the “wrong” gender suffered because of the operation and subsequent treatment, and many have reportedly changed gender as adults. Furthermore, some authors have argued that minimal interventions in early childhood are most appropriate, especially as tolerance and understanding of intersex genitalia grows in the United States.
Genetic Information
New genetic techniques present many ethical issues in DBP. Perhaps the most obvious is that each year seems to bring new possibilities for prenatal diagnosis, giving parents an opportunity to exercise the option of terminating a pregnancy and preventing the birth of a child with a disability. Although a woman’s right to an abortion has been protected by the 1973 Supreme Court ruling Roe v. Wade,36a there is widespread opposition to abortion in the United States. Reasonable people can disagree on whether prenatal testing and termination reduces human suffering or constitutes disrespect for life. Some people believe that a fetus is a human being entitled to the same protections as any other liveborn person, and because people in the United States have generally rejected arguments for active euthanasia in children with disabilities, it is wrong to terminate a pregnancy on the basis of prenatal diagnosis. Other people support U.S. laws and custom that define life as beginning approximately when a fetus is able to survive outside the womb; if a woman has the right to choose to carry a pregnancy to term, then certainly she and her family can decide whether to use prenatal testing to help ensure a healthy baby.
Philosopher Peter Singer and others have offered a third approach.37 Singer argues that personhood does not begin until sometime in the first year of life, when a human being is capable of interacting purposefully with the environment and begins to recognize the self as an independent being. According to this definition of personhood, termination of pregnancy and active euthanasia in the neonatal period for a baby with profound disabilities may be morally appropriate actions. However, the current consensus in the United States is that brainstem activity is sufficient to define life: Babies with anencephaly and individuals in a persistent vegetative state—conditions in which brainstem function may be present—are considered live persons, and state laws for brain death require absence of brainstem function.
Universal neonatal screening programs to prevent the neurodevelopmental consequences of congenital hypothyroidism or phenylketonuria also have widespread support and have substantially reduced the prevalence of mental retardation.38 As neonatal screening programs for genetic conditions expand, however, new ethical issues arise. Some authors have argued that the high number of false-positive results in universal screening programs constitutes unacceptable morbidity for affected families, whereas others are concerned that identifying conditions with no simple intervention is unfair. Genetic testing in general often reveals information not only about the patient, but about the patient’s family and about future generations. As in genetic tests for specific individuals, universal neonatal screening often produces results that have implications for entire families, many of whom may not have consented to revealing such information or wanting to know such information. Once predicative genetic information is known, it cannot be “unknown,” and there is no simple way to offer extended family members individual testing without causing emotional discomfort or exposing the affected individual. This is a difficult situation particularly when the medical condition has no specific cure, and such issues are best considered before such diagnostic tests are offered. Currently in the United States, there is a consensus that universal neonatal screening should be restricted to conditions for which early interventions and treatments are available,38a though a strong argument can be made for newborn screening to understand the natural history of metabolic variants of rare conditions.38b,38c Furthermore, when a genetic diagnosis has implications for family members, physicians have some obligation to inform them of the possibility for testing and treatment.
Genetic information may also have implications outside of the strict health care context. For example, predictive genetic information can have negative implications in the areas of employment and insurance for patients and/or family members. Genetic discrimination can occur when either an employer or an insurance company uses an individual’s predictive genetic information to refuse employment or insurance opportunities out of a fear that a genetic marker indicates a chance that the individual will become ill or disabled or will have a child with a disability.39 Although many legal commentators agree that such treatment should be viewed as illegal discrimination, courts have not offered definitive rulings on the issue. This may also be interpreted as good news: in view of the technology that has been available at least since the 1990s, it is reassuring that there have been no major cases of genetic discrimination.
Research on genetic issues adds yet another level of complexity to all of these ethical issues. Informed consent is particularly difficult, and provisions for communicating with family members must be determined ahead of time. For example, at least one state has considered requiring consent from all family members when genetic research is undertaken. Furthermore, storing samples and maintaining privacy require careful consideration, and researchers need to determine what to do if new information that would affect former research subjects becomes available. Finally, researchers may confront social and political consequences of their research results. Identifying genetic predispositions for stigmatizing conditions, particularly in vulnerable populations, can harm an entire population. For example, the genetics of cognitive ability has been related to race or ethnicity in nefarious ways since the 19th century.40
SCIENCE, PRACTICE, AND ADVOCACY
Privacy and Confidentiality
More commonly, developmental-behavioral pediatricians face dilemmas in protecting the confidentiality of their adolescent patients.41 In general, parents or guardians must consent to treatment for any person younger than 18 years, and such consent also brings the right to control medical information and make treatment decisions. Nearly every state provides exceptions for certain conditions regarding when adolescents can consent for care and thus control their own medical information. Such conditions typically include sexually transmitted infections, birth control, pregnancy, and, in some states, substance abuse treatment. The public health rationale for such laws is that adolescents are more likely to seek appropriate care if they believe that medical professionals will protect their confidentiality; in most such case, the medical team cannot share information about these specific conditions with anyone, including parents, without the teenaged patient’s consent. In practice, most adolescent patients are able to reveal such important diagnoses to their family with the practitioner’s support, especially because medical bills may eventually reveal the nature of the diagnosis.
The Legitimacy of Behavioral and Learning Disorders
A distinction continues to be made between developmental disorders and behavioral disorders, despite ample evidence of their considerable overlap. After centuries of blaming parents for disabilities, nearly everyone today understands that Down syndrome and cerebral palsy are medical conditions caused by natural processes. Mental illness in the United States, on the other hand, continues to carry the stigma of personal responsibility; for example, depression is different from diabetes, or so it seems to many individuals, despite research establishing the biological basis of behavioral and learning disorders. The popular media both stimulate and reflect public opinion in articles that question the biological legitimacy of disorders such as ADHD or learning disabilities. Such opinions are fueled by relatively vague definitions and limited diagnostic techniques for many disorders, by the “hidden” quality of these disabilities in comparison with cerebral palsy or Down syndrome, and by the complex interplay between biomedical and psychosocial manifestations of these disorder.
There is public controversy over both the diagnosis and treatment of common developmental-behavioral disorders. Increases in the diagnosis and use of prescription medications for ADHD, for example, has led to concern that physicians are overmedicating children. Although there are certainly cases of inappropriate diagnosis and treatment, most evidence suggests that the rise in prescriptions in stimulant medications reflects improved diagnosis and access to care. Indeed, some children with ADHD do not receive proper medical care despite overwhelming evidence of the value of medication in treating the core symptoms of inattention, impulsivity, and hyperactivity (for more detail, see Chapter 16).42 On the other hand, many children with behavioral disorders are being treated with four or five psychotropic medications; in view of the lack of data for such polypharmacy, the quality of care these children are receiving must be questioned.
Such unevenness in the diagnosis and treatment of developmental and behavioral disorders may reflect a critical national shortage in well-trained pediatric mental health professionals, particularly those who are bilingual and bicultural. According to the 1999 Report of the Surgeon General on Mental Health, 10% to 20% of children in the United States meet diagnostic criteria for a behavioral disorder, but fewer than one in every five of these children receive appropriate mental health treatment. On the other hand, access to services may partly account for the evidence that white boys attending private schools are particularly likely to receive a diagnosis of specific learning disabilities.43 Families with resources to obtain proper evaluations are better able to aid their children in obtaining accommodations in school and on standardized tests.
Subtle and inadvertent discrimination may also play a role in the diagnostic labels applied to certain children. Because of the lack of biological markers for most developmental and behavioral disorders, clinical judgment may be subject to bias. For example, although the diagnosis of mental retardation includes the use of standardized testing instruments, it remains a clinical diagnosis,44 and mental retardation is much more likely to be diagnosed in black boys than in children of other groups.45,46 Although such diagnostic labels may lead to individualized educational services, such labels frequently lower expectations and contribute to poor achievement.47
Although diagnosis of developmental-behavioral disorders only occasionally requires negotiation with parents, treatment is often a matter of some contention. It is a relatively straightforward matter that the health care practitioner should refuse to prescribe medication when it is not indicated, even if the family or schoolteacher seems eager for the child to begin pharmacotherapy. The more difficult situation is that in which families oppose medication despite abundant evidence that the child would benefit from it. Physicians are obligated to report instances of medical neglect to state authorities, but whereas failure of a parent to give insulin for diabetes would prompt state intervention, it is unlikely that anyone would force a family to provide methylphenidate for ADHD. In the future, U.S. society may view behavioral disorders as sufficiently legitimate to require appropriate treatment in all cases; until then, the developmental-behavioral practitioner must educate the family and hope that patience and follow-up are sufficient.
Although some families refuse treatment with medications, many more seek complementary and alternative medical treatment. Parents are particularly eager for simple solutions to chronic conditions such as autism and cerebral palsy, and the desire for “natural” treatments appears strong for almost all behavioral and developmental disorders. For most alternative treatments, there is little evidence of safety or efficacy, and many are quite expensive. Complementary and alternative medicine is an area in which more evidence of benefits and adverse effects is needed, and some research is in progress (for more details, see Chapter 8E). Although the practitioner may be frustrated by family’s attention to alternative treatments, it is important to remember that many improvements in diagnosis and treatment of developmental and behavioral disorders have resulted from families’ advocating for their children and challenging the status quo. By keeping an open mind and working with families over time, the developmental-behavioral practitioner can help families conserve their resources and focus on treatments that are most likely to benefit their children.
Developmental-Behavioral Practitioner as Scientist and as Advocate
There can be little doubt that commitment to high-quality scientific research is one critical component to solving many of the dilemmas arising in the clinical practice of DBP. As the biological understanding of developmental and behavioral disorders grows, so should the legitimacy of diagnosis and treatment. Better diagnostic tools can reduce bias, and improved treatment can improve collaboration between parents and clinicians. Understanding specific causal mechanisms should lead to prevention and better treatment and can even help build a widespread consensus that every child and family deserves access to high-quality mental health treatment (for more detail, see Chapter 3). Even if not directly involved in research, practitioners can serve as an educator and ambassador: They are obligated to teach families and the public about scientific principles that guide their practice and to continue to better understand the causes and treatments of behavioral disorders.
Advances in science also lead to new ethical dilemmas, of course, as suggested by the possibilities of innovative genetic and surgical techniques. Furthermore, the advantages of new medical interventions tend to accrue to those who already enjoy the best health and most wealth, thus further exacerbating underlying inequities in U.S. society. This suggests a continuing role for the developmental-behavioral practitioner as an advocate for broader social change. For some practitioners, this may mean participating in local school and child care centers or providing community education opportunities. Others may engage the legislative process to improve access to health care, reduce economic inequity, or improve professional standards. Practitioners should at least be informed about critical child health issues and should recognize that advocacy can be learned just as can any other skill in medicine.47a
This is not to suggest that practitioners are not also obligated at a policy level to work to build consensus on critical issues in DBP. For example, there is ample evidence that children who grow up in poverty experience profound developmental and behavioral consequences, and there seems to be broad social consensus that whatever the personal and social causes of family poverty, children should not suffer. Although much political and academic debate focuses on issues at the beginning and end of life, not nearly enough attention seems to flow to the children who grow up in poverty. For example, resources continue to be devoted to the criminal justice system, whereas prevention programs that support families, improve child care, and improve mental health are chronically underfunded. International comparisons are instructive: Most European nations, for example, have created public systems that provide high-quality medical care to all children and buffer the effects of poverty on most children. The increased burden of illness for children of low socioeconomic status and of ethnic or racial minorities is unacceptable, and it is only partly explained by decreased access to care. At the highest level of moral reasoning, the developmental-behavioral practitioner is an advocate not just for the child in the office but for the well-being of all children.
1 Ad Hoc Committee on Medical Ethics. American College of Physicians Ethics Manual. Ann Intern Med. 1984;101:129-137. 263–274
2 Starr P. The social transformation of American medicine: The rise of a sovereign profession and the making of a vast industry. New York: Basic Books, 1983.
3 American Board of Internal Medicine Foundation, American College of Physicians-American Society of Internal Medicine Foundation, European Federation of Internal Medicine. Medical professionalism in the new millennium: A physician charter. Ann Intern Med. 2002;136:243-246.
4 Inui TS. A Flag in the Wind: Educating for Professionalism in Medicine. Washington, DC: Association of American Medical Colleges, 2003.
5 Faunce TA. Will international human rights subsume medical ethics? Intersection in the UNESCO Universal Bioethics Declaration. J Med Ethics. 2005;31:173-178.
6 United Nations Educational, Scientific, and Cultural Organization (UNESCO): Universal Declaration on Bioethics and Human Rights. Paris: UNESCO, 2005. (Available at: http://portal.unesco.org/shs/en/ev.php-URL_ID=1883&URL_DO=DO_TOPIC&URL_SECTION=201.html; accessed 2/25/07.)
7 Beauchamp TL, Childress JF. Principles of Biomedical Ethics, 4th ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 1994.
8 Gert B. Morality: Its Nature and Justification, rev. ed. New York: Oxford University Press, 2005.
9 Post SG, editor. Encyclopedia of Bioethics, 3rd ed., New York: Macmillan, 2004.
9a. Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479, 1965.
10 Bardon A. Ethics education and value prioritization among members of U.S. Hospital Ethics Committees. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 2004;14:395-406.
11 Siegler M. Searching for moral certainty in medicine: A proposal for a new model of the doctor-patient encounter. Bull N Y Acad Med. 1981;57:56-69.
12 American Society for Bioethics and Humanities. Core Competencies for Health Care Ethics Consultation. Glenview, IL: American Society for Bioethics and Humanities, 1998.
13 Walton O, Schalick I. History of disability: Medieval west. Albrecht GL, Mitchell DT, Snyder SL, et al, editors. Encyclopedia of Disability, 5. London: Sage Publications, 2005.
14 Meri JW, editor. Medieval Islamic Civilization, An Encyclopedia, nos. 1 and 2. New York: Taylor & Francis, 2006.
15 James W, Trent J. Inventing the Feeble Mind: A History of Mental Retardation in the United States. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1994.
16 Pernick MS. The black stork: Eugenics and the death of “defective” babies in American medicine and motion pictures since 1915. New York: Oxford University Press, 1996.
16a. Buck v. Bell, 274 U.S. 200, 1927.
17 Braddock DL, Parish SL. An Institutional History of Disability. In: Albrecht GL, Seelman KD, Bury M, editors. Handbook of Disability Studies. New York: Sage Publications; 2000:11-68.
18 Fleischer D, Zames F. The disability rights movement: From charity to confrontation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2001.
19 Shorter E. The Kennedy Family and the Story of Mental Retardation. Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 2000.
20 Shapiro JP. No pity: People with disabilities forging a new civil rights movement. New York: Times Books, 1994.
21 Liachowitz CH. Disability as a Social Construct: Legislative Roots. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1988.
22 Robertson JA. Extreme prematurity and parental rights after Baby Doe. Hastings Center Rep. 2004;34(4):32-39.
23 Lee SK, Penner PL, Cox M. Comparison of the attitudes of health care professionals and parents toward active treatment of very low birth weight infants. Pediatrics. 1991;88:110-114.
24 Lee SK, Penner PL, Cox M. Impact of very low birth weight infants on the family and its relationship to parental attitudes. Pediatrics. 1991;88:105-109.
25 American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics. Informed consent, parental permission, and assent in pediatric practice. Pediatrics. 1995;95:314-317.
26 American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics. Ethics and the care of critically ill infants and children. Pediatrics. 1996;98:149-152.
27 Kopelman LM. Rejecting the Baby Doe rules and defending a “negative” analysis of the Best Interests Standard. J Med Philos. 2005;30:331-352.
28 Kopelman LM. Are the 21-year-old Baby Doe rules misunderstood or mistaken? Pediatrics. 2005;115:797-802.
29 Cerminara K, Goodman K: Key events in the case of Theresa Marie Schiavo. Miami: University of Miami Ethics Programs, Last updated 21-Aug-2006. (Available at: http://www.miami.edu/ethics2/schiavo/timeline.htm; accessed 2/25/07.)
30 Miller PS. The impact of assisted suicide on persons with disabilities-Is it a right without freedom? Issues Law Med. 1993;9:47-62.
31 Nelson LJ. Respect for the developmentally disabled and forgoing life-sustaining treatment. Ment Retard Dev Disabil Res Rev. 2003;9:3-9.
32 Balkany T, Hodges AV, Goodman K. Ethics of cochlear implantation in young children. Otolaryngol Head Neck Surg. 1999;121:673-675.
33 Reefhuis J, Honein MA, Whitney CG, et al. Risk of bacterial meningitis in children with cochlear implants. N Engl J Med. 2003;349:435-445.
34 Parens E, editor. Surgically Shaping Children: Technology, Ethics and the Pursuit of Normality. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2006.
35 Kipnis K, Diamond M. Pediatric ethics and the surgical assignment of sex. Clin Ethics. 1998;9:398-410.
36 Kuhnle U, Krahl W. The impact of culture on sex assignment and gender development in intersex patients. Perspect Biol Med. 2002;45:85-103.
36a. Roe v. Wade, 410 U.S. 113, 1973.
37 Singer P. Practical Ethics, 2nd ed. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
38 Brosco JP, Mattingly M, Sanders LM. Impact of specific medical interventions on reducing the prevalence of mental retardation. Arch Pediatr Adolesc Med. 2006;160:302-309.
38a. Botkin JR, Clayton EW, Fost NC, Burke W, Murray TH, Baily MA, Wilfond B, Berg A, Ross LF. Newborn screening technology: proceed with caution. Pediatrics. 2006;117(5):1793-1799.
38b. Howell RR. We need expanded newborn screening. Pediatrics. 2006;117(5):1800-1805.
38c. Bailey DBJr, Skinner D, Warren SF. Newborn screening for developmental disabilities: reframing presumptive benefit. Am J Public Health. 2005;95(11):1889-1893.
39 Miller PS. Is There a pink slip in my genes? Genetic discrimination in the workplace. Health Care Law Policy. 2000;3:225-237.
40 Brosco JP. History and ethics in public health research. Prof Ethics. 2003;11(3):45-64.
41 Anderson SL, Schaechter J, Brosco JP. Adolescent patients and their confidentiality: Staying within legal bounds. Contemp Pediatr. 2005;22:54-64.
42 U.S. Department of Health and Human Services. Mental Health: A Report of the Surgeon General. Rockville, MD: National Institutes of Health, National Institute of Mental Health, Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration, Center for Mental Health Services, 1999.
43 Weiss KR: New test-taking skill: Working the system. The Los Angeles Times, January 9, 2000, p A1.
44 American Association on Mental Retardation. Mental Retardation: Definition, Classification, and Systems of Supports, 10th ed. Washington, DC: American Association on Mental Retardation, 2002.
45 Yeargin-Allsopp M, Drews C, Decoufle P, et al. Mild mental retardation in black and white children in metropolitan Atlanta: A case-control study. Am J Public Health. 1995;85:324-328.
46 Naglieri JA, Rojahn JL. Intellectual classification of black and white children in special education programs using the WISC-III and the Cognitive Assessment System. Am J Ment Retard. 2001;106:359-367.
47 Losen D, Orfield G, editors. Racial Inequity in Special Education. Boston: Harvard Education Publishing Group, 2002.
47a. Sanders LM, Robinson TN, Forster LQ, Plax K, Brosco JP, Brito A. Evidence-based community pediatrics: building a bridge from bedside to neighborhood. Pediatrics. 2005;115(4 Suppl):1142-1147.
48 UNESCO. Explanatory Memorandum on the Elaboration of the Preliminary Draft Declaration on Universal Norms of Bioethics. Paris: UNESCO, 2005.
49 American Medical Association. Guidelines for ethics committees in health care institutions. JAMA. 1985;253:2698-2699.
50 American Academy of Pediatrics Committee on Bioethics. Institutional ethics committees. Committee on Bioethics. Pediatrics. 2001;107:205-209.
51 National Dissemination Center for Children with Disabilities (NICHCY). The Education of Children and Youth with Special Needs: What Do the Laws Say? Washington, DC: NICHCY, October 1996.
52 U.S. Equal Employment Opportunity Commission. Americans with Disabilities Act: Questions and answers. Washington, DC: U.S Department of Justice, Civil Rights Division, U.S. Equal Employment Opportunity Commission, 2002;1-22.
53 Disability Programs and Resource Center: A Chronology of the Disability Rights Movement. San Francisco: San Francisco State University, 2006. (Available at: http://www.sfsu.edu/∼hrdpu/chron.htm; accessed 2/22/07.)
54 General Medical Council. Good Medical Practice. London: General Medical Council; 1998. Booklet available at http://www.gmc.uk.org/guidance/good_medical_practice/GMC_GMP.pdf.
55 Anderson M, Cohen J, Hallock J, Kassebaum D, Turn-bull J, Whitcomb M. Learning objectives for medical student education-guidelines for medical schools. Academic Medicine. 1999;74:13-18.
* Nancy Cruzan nearly died in a car accident in 1983 but continued living in a persistent vegetative state. Her parents’ request some years later that hydration and nutrition be withheld led the U.S. Supreme Court to rule that the due process clause of the U.S. Constitution allowed competent persons to refuse medical care. However, the Court also allowed states to determine what degree of evidence is necessary to determine a person’s wishes, which led to nationwide interest in advanced directives. Cruzan died in 1990 when the state court ruled that there was sufficient evidence of her wishes to order the removal of her feeding tube.
* Buck is among the most famous and prolific writers in U.S. history; her work earned both Pulitzer and Nobel prizes for literature in the early 20th century. Buck’s first daughter was born with phenylketonuria and developed profound mental retardation, and Buck wrote movingly and spoke publicly about her daughter at a time when shame was still common for parents.
† Rogers, the singing cowboy of movie and radio fame, was a childhood hero to many in the mid-20th century United States. His wife, actress Dale Evans, teamed up with him on popular entertainment shows to help explain the story of their daughter, Robin Elizabeth, who was born with Down syndrome.
* Roberts was admitted to the University of California at Berkeley in 1962, despite administration concerns that his polio-related paralysis should disqualify him. Roberts became a leader in the disability rights movement and has been called the “father of independent living.”
† After initially being discouraged from attending school because of her disability, Heumann became one of the key shaping forces of federal disability policy starting in the 1970s. By the end of the 20th century, she had become Assistant Secretary of Education; over the previous three decades, she had worked to develop the regulations (Section 504) and laws (Americans with Disabilities Education Act) that together help guarantee civil rights to persons with disabilities.
* Schiavo suffered cardiopulmonary arrest in 1990 and eventually was determined to be in a persistent vegetative state. Her husband petitioned the Florida court system to remove her feeding tube in 1998, an action that was opposed by her parents. After more than a dozen court decisions supporting her husband’s argument that Schiavo would not want to live in a persistent vegetative state, the tube was removed, and she died in March 2005. In the last 2 years of her life, President George W. Bush, the U.S. Congress, Florida Governor Jeb Bush, and the Florida state legislature attempted to prevent removal of the feeding tube.