7. Human rights and the mentally ill

Published on 12/05/2015 by admin

Filed under Internal Medicine

Last modified 22/04/2025

Print this page

rate 1 star rate 2 star rate 3 star rate 4 star rate 5 star
Your rating: none, Average: 0 (0 votes)

This article have been viewed 1648 times

CHAPTER 7. Human rights and the mentally ill
L earning objectives

▪ Discuss critically the nursing implications of human rights to and in mental health.
▪ Discuss critically the negative impact of stigmatisation, prejudice and discrimination against people with mental illness.
▪ Examine critically the ways in which a human rights approach to mental health might not always benefit the mentally ill.
▪ Discuss critically the nature and use of psychiatric advance directives (‘Ulysses contracts’) in mental health.
▪ Explore ways in which members of the nursing profession might improve its advocacy of people with mental health problems and severe mental illnesses.

I ntroduction

Discussions on patients’ rights to and in health care have tended to have as their focus persons with ‘physical health’ problems. While important, this focus has nevertheless been at the expense of attention being given to the moral entitlements of people with ‘mental health’ problems. Significantly, the subject of moral rights and the mentally ill has been relatively neglected in mainstream bioethics discourse (Johnstone 2001, 1995; Christensen 1997). In light of the past neglect of mental health care ethics in both the mainstream bioethics and nursing literature, and the unique features of psychiatric ethics that are being increasingly recognised (Hughes & Fulford 2005), ‘special’ attention to the moral plight of the mentally ill is warranted. In this chapter, a brief overview will be provided of some of the disproportionate, and hence unjust burdens, that people with mental illness have to carry in the cultural context of Australia. While drawing primarily on the Australian experience, this discussion nonetheless has relevance for nurses working in other countries.

P revalence of mental illness

The term ‘mental illness’ is generally used to describe ‘a number of diagnosable disorders that significantly interfere with an individual’s cognitive, emotional and social abilities’ (Council of Australian Governments [COAG] 2006: 1). Such disorders may include, but are not limited to, depression, bipolar disorder, schizophrenia and also states of extreme psychological distress (COAG 2006; Australian Institute of Health and Welfare [AIHW] 2005).
According to estimates by the World Health Organization (WHO), over 450 million people suffer from a mental or behaviour disorder (WHO 2001a: 3). Significantly, only a small minority of these people ‘receive even the most basic treatment’ (WHO 2001a: 3). Most individuals with mental illness, WHO asserts, ‘are left to cope as best they can with their private burdens such as depression, dementia, schizophrenia, and substance dependence’ (WHO 2001a: 3).
In Australia, it is estimated that a mental illness and/or mental health problem will affect more than one in five (20%) of the adult population in their lifetime, and between 10–15% of young people in any one year (AIHW 2005). According to government sources, mental disorders constitute the leading cause of disability in Australia, and account for an estimated 27% of the total years lost due to disability, at a cost of around $20 billion annually through lost productivity and participation in the workforce (AIHW 2005; COAG 2006).

S tigma, prejudice and discrimination against the mentally ill

It is accepted internationally that people suffering from mental health disorders, mental illness and other mental health-related problems are among the most stigmatised, discriminated against, marginalised, disadvantaged and hence vulnerable individuals in society (WHO 2001a; Guimón 2001; Johnstone 2001). 1
Compounding the vulnerability of people with mental illness are the harmful effects of stigma itself (referred to as ‘iatrogenic stigma’) (Sartorius 2002; Sartorius & Schulze 2005). In order to understand why and how the process of stigmatisation, prejudice and discrimination work to marginalise, disadvantage and hurt people with mental health disorders and illnesses, some clarification of the notions of ‘stigma’, ‘prejudice’ and ‘discrimination’ is required here, and is provided below.

S tigma

Stigma (from Latin via Greek meaning ‘brand’ or ‘bodily sign’) is literally a distinguishing mark of social disgrace. It presupposes the acquisition of an attribute or attributes that others (usually those who are dominant members of a mainstream culture or group) find or regard as deeply discrediting (personally, socially and morally) and, importantly, who have the power to discredit those deemed ‘marked’ as socially disgraced (Goffman 1963; Link et al 2004; Link & Phelan 2006). What is regarded as a ‘distinguishing mark of social disgrace’, however, and what impact it will ultimately have on people, will depend on the culture from which it has originated and what that culture deems as being ‘deviant’ (Link et al 2004).
According to Jones et al (1984) the incidence and impact of a given stigmatised ‘characteristic’ or ‘condition’ will depend on the following five dimensions:
Concealability — refers to how obvious a characteristic is and the degree to which it can be concealed from others
Disruptiveness — refers to ‘the extent to which a mark strains or obstructs interpersonal interactions’
Aesthetics — refers to the extent to which a mark elicits an ‘affective reaction of disgust’
Origin — refers to ‘how the condition came into being’ and particularly whether the marked person was ‘responsible’ for the condition (e.g. whether genetic, accidental or self-caused)
Peril — refers to ‘feelings of danger or threat that the mark indicates in others’ (cited in Link et al 2004: 512).
The process of stigmatisation becomes problematic when it evolves into a situation in which an individual is disqualified from full social and cultural acceptance on the basis of his or her carrying a given ‘distinguishing mark of social disgrace’ (e.g. being immigrant, disabled, homosexual, mentally ill, old etc.) (Goffman 1963). Inevitably this means that stigma almost always carries with it commensurate processes of discrimination; that is, the unfair treatment of persons on the basis of their ‘distinguishing mark(s)’. This treatment is unfair since judgments are made on the somewhat arbitrary basis of morally irrelevant distinguishing marks, rather than on moral considerations per se; hence the notion that stigma and stigmatisation are unjustly discriminatory. This outcome is unethical since, by focusing on one (or more) arbitrary characteristic(s) of a person (e.g. the marks that may ‘distinguish them’), stigma and discrimination undermine the moral worth (dignity) of a person (results in them ‘losing face’, if you will) and thus dehumanises them. The stigmatising and (negative) discriminatory treatment of persons thus stands in contradistinction to the respectful treatment of persons — that is, responses to persons that are guided by profoundly moral considerations, not merely arbitrary ones.
It is important to note that stigma can involve both ‘public’ (public-stigma) and ‘self’ (self-stigma) reactions. Public-stigma has been described as comprising ‘reactions of the general public towards a group based on stigma about that group’, and as consisting of three elements: stereotypes, prejudice and discrimination, that occur in ‘the context of power differences and leads to reactions of the general public towards the stigmatized groups as a result of stigma’ (Rüsch et al 2005: 530 & 531). Self-stigma, in contrast, refers to ‘reactions of individuals who belong to a stigmatized group and turn the stigmatizing attitudes against themselves’ (Rüsch et al 2005: 531). Like public-stigma, self-stigma also consists of three elements: stereotypes, prejudice and discrimination, but with the notable distinction that all three tend to be strongly aligned with public-stigmatisation, with individuals internalising the negative public attitudes against themselves; for example ‘That’s right; I am weak and unable to care for myself’ (Rüsch et al 2005: 531).
In the case of mental illness and mental health problems, stigmas globally have been found to be ‘widely supported by the general public’ (Rüsch et al 2005: 532; see also Martin et al 2000). While some have suggested that the increase in demand for mental health services in some countries can be taken as a key indicator that stigma is beginning to decline in those countries, others are more circumspect (Mojtabai 2007). Rüsch et al (2005), for example, suggest that, overall, mental illness has in fact become even more stigmatised over the last decade. Furthermore, in keeping with the under-recognition of the negative effects of stigma generally on people’s life chances and lives, the stigmatisation of the mentally ill is also under-recognised — contributing further to the ‘double jeopardy’ that people with mental illness face on account of being both mentally ill and stigmatised (Link & Phelan 2006).
The double jeopardy faced by people with mental illnesses (especially when ‘multiple stigmatising factors’ are also in play [Link & Phelan 2001]) is extremely burdensome. As the US Department of Health and Human Services (1999: viii) noted in its landmark report Mental Health (the first Surgeon General report ever issued on the topic), ‘stigma tragically deprives people of their dignity and interferes with their full participation in society’.
In recent years there has been increasing recognition that mental illness is an illness that ‘strikes with a two-edged sword’ (Corrigan et al 2004), which in turn imposes on its sufferers ‘a double problem’ (Rüsch et al 2005). Corrigan et al (2004: 489) explain:
On the one side, people must struggle with the symptoms and disabilities that prevent them from achieving many of their life goals. On the other, the stigma of mental illness further hampers their opportunities and aspirations.
Stigma not only hampers the opportunities and aspirations of people with mental illness, however. As Hocking (2003: S47) points out, people’s experiences of stigma and prejudices associated with mental illnesses can, in fact, be as distressing as the symptoms of the illnesses themselves. Moreover, as research has shown, in addition to causing anger, embarrassment, fear and isolation, the stigmatising attitudes and behaviours of people can exacerbate an illness and can also lead to depression and even suicide in those most affected (Dinos et al 2004; Hocking 2003). What is especially worrying, however, is that stigma has also been identified as ‘a significant barrier’ to the mentally ill getting needed care and treatment, and even as being ‘the main obstacle to a better life for the many hundreds of millions of people suffering from mental disorders and their consequences’ worldwide (Sartorius 2002: 1471; see also Rüsch et al 2005; Sartorius & Schulze 2005).
Stigma has become so associated with mental illness that some have suggested that ‘recovery’, in part, also involves ‘taking back control and seeing oneself as more than a stigmatising label’ (Diesfeld & Freckelton 2006: 93). Significantly, Australian research has also found that, for people with mental illnesses and their families, less stigma is the ‘number one thing that would make their lives better’ (Hocking 2003: S46).

P rejudice and discrimination

The term prejudice (literally to ‘prejudge’ without adequate facts) may be defined as ‘any belief (especially an unfavourable one), whether correct or incorrect, held without proper consideration of, or sometimes in defiance of, the evidence’ (Flew & Priest 2002: 326). The counterpart of prejudice is discrimination. Discrimination, in turn, may be broadly defined as ‘the unfair treatment of a person, racial group, minority, etc, based on prejudice’.
People with mental illnesses (or a past history of mental illnesses) are vulnerable to both direct and indirect/intentional and unintentional discrimination in a variety of contexts including health care, research, and other social domains where the ‘public prefers to maintain social distance from persons with mental health problems’ (Muroff et al 2006: 129; see also Byrne 1997; Corrigan et al 2004; Martin et al 2000; Rüsch et al 2005). And although there have been significant advances made in mental health over the past several decades, international studies have repeatedly found that stigma and discrimination (both direct and indirect) against the mentally ill (especially those with psychotic illnesses) is pervasive, and continues to have a negative influence on ‘how a psychiatric diagnosis is accepted, whether treatment will be adhered to and how people with mental illness function in the world’ (Dinos et al 2004: 176; see also Glozier et al 2006).
In Australia, for example, a 1993 national inquiry into the human rights of people with mental illness found that people affected by mental illness suffered from ‘widespread, systematic discrimination and are consistently denied the rights and services to which they are entitled’ (Burdekin et al 1993: 870). The inquiry also found that discrimination was particularly widespread in mainstream society, with the mentally ill experiencing ‘stigma and discrimination in almost every aspect of their lives’, ranging from restrictions on eligibility for insurance and superannuation schemes, to employment, education and training (Burdekin et al 1993: 925). Equally disturbing was the inquiry’s additional finding that underpinning this discrimination were deeply ingrained (and often structurally reinforced) societal attitudes of fear, ignorance and intolerance of mental illness and mental health disorders.
A decade later, a nationwide review of the experiences of users and providers of community-based mental health services in Australia found that the human rights of mentally ill persons (including their right of access to appropriate mental health services) continue to be violated (Groom & Hickie 2003; Groom et al 2003; see also Armstrong 2003, 2000; Muir-Cochrane et al 2002). Disturbingly, people of non-English speaking backgrounds in Australia (on account of being ‘mentally ill’, ‘ethnic’, and stigmatised on both these counts) have been identified as being in ‘multiple jeopardy’ of being discriminated against and suffering the burden of their mental illnesses and diseases (Victorian Government, Department of Human Services 2006). Tragically, the unjust burden of suffering associated with stigma, prejudice and discrimination against the mentally ill is not confined to the cultural context of Australia. According to WHO (2001a: 3), mental ill-health and the burden of suffering associated with it (including that imposed by stigma and discrimination) has been largely ignored or neglected in most parts of the world.

A human rights approach to protecting the mentally ill

In Australia, as in other countries, it has become increasingly recognised at a social, cultural and political level that people suffering from mental illnesses, mental health disorders and other mental health-related problems need to be protected from abuse and neglect, something which for a variety of reasons they are especially vulnerable to experiencing. This need of protection has also been recognised at an international level as evident by the United Nations General Assembly’s adoption in 1991 of the principles for ‘The Protection of Persons with Mental Illness and for the Improvement of Mental Health Care’ and, more recently, by the WHO’s release of its World Health Report 2001, ‘Mental Health: New Understanding, New Hope’ (WHO 2001a).
In attempting to secure protection of the mentally ill and disordered from abuse and neglect, a human rights model of mental health care ethics has been adopted. Underpinning the selection of this model is the view that ‘all people have fundamental human rights’ and that people with mental health problems or disorders should not be precluded from having or exercising these rights just because of their mental health difficulties. As the Mental Health Consumer Outcomes Task Force argued over a decade ago (1995: ix):
The diagnosis of mental health problems or mental disorder is not an excuse for inappropriately limiting their [people with mental health problems or disorders] rights.
In March 1991, the Australian Health Ministers acknowledged and accepted the above viewpoint, and adopted, as part of Australia’s national mental health strategy, the final report of the Mental Health Consumer Outcomes Task Force, titled Mental Health Statement of Rights and Responsibilities. First published in 1991 and reprinted five times since its initial publication (latest edition 2000), this document stands as an influential guiding force behind other public policy initiatives and statements such as the National Mental Health Policy (Australian Health Ministers 1992), the National safety priorities in mental health: a national plan for reducing harm (National Mental Health Working Group 2005), as well as health care professional practice in mental health care settings.
The Mental Health Statement of Rights and Responsibilities makes explicit and seeks to inform a range of stakeholders of a number of key rights (in fact, a mixture of moral, civil and legal rights) affecting ‘individuals seeking promotion or enhancement of mental health or care and protection when suffering mental health problems or mental disorders’ (Mental Health Consumer Outcomes Task Force 1995: 1). Included in its list are consumers’ rights to:
▪ access adequate, high-quality and culturally appropriate mental health care services
▪ make informed choices about care and treatment
▪ privacy, dignity and respect
▪ be treated fairly
▪ mechanisms of complaint and redress
▪ advocacy
▪ have legislation affirm their fundamental rights
▪ have mental health legislation reviewed and updated as necessary
▪ have access to relatives and friends
▪ rehabilitation
▪ ‘the right equal to other citizens to health care, income maintenance, education, employment, housing, transport, legal services, equitable health and other insurance and leisure appropriate to one’s age’ (Mental Health Consumer Outcomes Task Force 1995: 1).
As well as specifying a number of key rights, the statement also lists key responsibilities; included here are mental health consumers’ responsibilities to ‘respect the human worth and dignity of other people; and to participate as far as possible in reasonable treatment and rehabilitation processes’ (Mental Health Consumer Outcomes Task Force 1995: 2). The rights and responsibilities of service providers, carers and advocates are also listed and are framed in a way that primarily reflects the correlative duties they have in response to the consumer rights listed above.

P roblems associated with a human rights approach to mental health care ethics

At first glance, the content and intent of the Mental Health Statement of Rights and Responsibilities (referred to earlier) seems to provide an important step forward towards the protection of the human rights of people made vulnerable by mental health problems. On closer examination, however, there is room to suggest that the statement may, in reality, offer those working in the field little guidance on what to do when faced with morally problematic situations involving people who are mentally ill, mentally unwell, mentally disordered or whatever other description may be appropriate of someone experiencing a mental health problem. One reason for this relates to the problematic nature of a human rights approach to ethics itself (discussed earlier in Chapter 3 of this book). Let us consider this claim further.
Human rights claims entail a range of ‘special interests’ deserving protection for a variety of reasons. Human rights include moral rights, legal rights, civil rights and so forth, and thus do not exclusively concern moral rights. Of pertinence to this discussion is the moral rights aspect of human rights.
As previously explained, a moral right can be defined as a special interest or entitlement which a person has and which ought to be protected for moral reasons. Having a moral right usually entails that another has a corresponding duty to respect that right. Fulfilling a corresponding duty can involve either doing something ‘positive’ to benefit a person claiming a particular right or, alternatively, refraining from doing something ‘negative’ which could harm a person claiming a particular right. For example, if a patient claims the right to make an informed choice concerning prescribed psychotropic medication or electroconvulsive therapy (ECT), this imposes on an attending health care professional a corresponding duty to ensure that the patient is fully informed about the therapeutic effects and the adverse side effects of the treatments in question as well as to respect the patient’s choice to either accept or refuse the treatment, even where the health professional may not agree with the ultimate choice made. The moral force of the right’s claim in this instance is such that if an attending health care professional does not uphold or violates the patient’s choice in regard to the treatment options considered, that patient would probably feel wronged or that a serious injustice had been done. The health care professional in turn could be judged, criticised and possibly even censured on grounds of having infringed the patient’s rights.
For example, should the role of, and the duty to act as, an advocate fall to an attending health care professional (who may or may not have intimate knowledge of the mentally ill person)? Or a family member (who, while having intimate knowledge of the mentally ill person, may for some reason be estranged from him or her)? Or a friend (who has no legal relationship with the person, but nevertheless has the person’s best interests at heart)? Or a lawyer or some other legal representative (who, despite having the legal authority to act on behalf of the person, may be a complete stranger and not really be in a position to advocate the person’s ‘best interests’ at all)? How is a matter of this nature to be decided and by whom? There may be no easy answers to the questions posed. An additional problem concerns the philosophical issue of whether human rights are of a nature that allows another to validly act as a ‘surrogate decision-maker’ and make rights claims ‘by proxy’ on behalf of another. To put this another way, is the freedom to exercise a human right something that can be ‘abdicated’ to another? Or does this defeat the whole purpose of having individual human rights in the first place?
Another difficulty is that rights can conflict and compete with one another. For example, the patient’s stated right to have ‘access to family and friends’ could seriously conflict with the family’s and friend’s moral interests and entitlements to be spared the certain harms that might flow from contact; for example, in the case of a patient who is physically violent and has demonstrable homicidal tendencies. In a case such as this, the patient’s right to privacy and confidentiality might also stand in serious conflict with the moral interests of family and friends to be warned of a possible threat to their safety and wellbeing; for example, in instances where the client has disclosed a serious intention to kill a given person, as tragically happened in the 1974 American legal case Tarasoff v Regents of the University of California (discussed in Chapter 6). While a human rights approach to ethics may tell us what rights people have, it offers very little guidance in regard to what should be done when stated rights conflict and compete with one another.
Related to the above is the additional difficulty of establishing the extent to which a patient’s rights claim entails a correlative duty. Consider, for example, a person’s right to access appropriate and quality mental health care services. Consider also that such a claim may be extremely difficult to uphold in instances where services are either seriously under-resourced or simply do not exist (such as in rural and remote areas). Here difficult questions arise concerning who or what has a corresponding duty to respond to a mentally ill person’s rights in this instance: Is it an individual nurse? another mental health worker? a mental health service? a general hospital? family? friends? the state? a philanthropist? or some other entity? Compounding this difficulty is the problem of competing rights claims. For example, a number of persons might make equally deserving claims to mental health care services (as they do) but, because of a shortage of resources, it is genuinely difficult to satisfy the rights claims of all persons equally. Compounding these difficulties still further is the additional question of whether it makes sense to even claim a right to something that does not exist, in this instance, a particular type of health care service in a particular region? Further, is it reasonable to condemn someone for not providing a service where no such service exists or where existing services have been totally exhausted? There may be no satisfactory answers to these questions.
Finally there is the paradoxical problem of a human rights approach to mental health care ethics being abused to advance dominant political interests. For instance, trends over the past four decades favouring the deinstitutionalisation of the mentally ill might be cynically appraised as having been motivated not by humane concern for people with mental health problems confined to institutional care, but by blatant political interest in reducing the cost (both financial and political) of institutionalised mental health care services around the country — some of which were shown to be seriously substandard (see, e.g. the publicly documented cases of the Chelmsford Hospital in New South Wales [Bromberger & Fife-Yeomans 1991], Ward 10B of Townsville Hospital in Queensland [Carter 1991], and the Lakeside Hospital in Victoria [Burdekin et al 1993: 870]). Consider the following.
In his controversial text Nowhere to Go, Torrey (1988), an American psychiatrist, persuasively argues that sometimes rights (e.g. civil and legal rights) designed to protect the mentally ill often protect their ‘right’ to remain mentally ill. In illustrating this, Torrey (1988) cites an American case of a man suffering from schizophrenia and who was the subject of a committal hearing. The man had been refusing food, but was said to have been ingesting his own faeces. Although in a state of neglect and in need of institutional care and treatment, the man could not be institutionalised against his will without a court order. Significantly, while the court acknowledged that the man was eating his own faeces, it did not regard this as constituting a ‘danger to self’ (or to others, for that matter). The court subsequently upheld the man’s ‘civil liberty’ not to be institutionalised against his will. An important point to be drawn from this case is that while that man’s civil liberties (rights) were protected by the court in this instance, his genuine human welfare and wellbeing were not. As one observer cited by Torrey (1988: 31) phrased it, ‘we are protecting the civil liberties [of the mentally ill] much more adequately than we are protecting their minds and their lives’.
In light of the above discussion, it can be seen that a human rights approach to mental health care ethics can be problematic. One reason for this can be found in the nature of a rights approach to ethics itself and the difficulties which can be experienced in determining who has rights, who has corresponding duties to these rights, and how best to try and satisfy all valid rights claims of all people equally. Another difficulty is that what are sometimes put forward as moral rights are not, technically speaking, moral rights at all, but rather a mixture of civil rights (special interests and entitlements people have by virtue of being civilians), legal rights (special interests or entitlements bestowed by law and which ought to be protected for legal reasons) or institutional rights (special interests or entitlements bestowed by an institution in which one is participating in some way) — all of which have differing moral force. This mixture can confuse judgments on what is a morally correct course of action to take and can compound many of the problems outlined above.
An important question to arise here is: If statements on human rights and responsibilities in mental health care are so problematic, is there any point in having them? The short answer to this question is, yes. Whatever the faults, weaknesses and difficulties of such statements, they nevertheless achieve a number of important things:
▪ they help to remind patients, service providers, caregivers and the general community that people with mental health problems (including mental illness and mental health disorders) do have special interests and entitlements which ought to be respected and protected
▪ they help to inform stakeholders (patients, service providers, caregivers and the community) of what these special entitlements are and thereby provide a basis upon which respect for and protection of these can be demanded
▪ they help to delineate the special responsibilities that stakeholders (patients, service providers, caregivers and the community) all have in ensuring the promotion and protection of people’s special interests and entitlements in mental health care and in promoting mental health generally
▪ they help to remind all stakeholders (patients, service providers, caregivers and the community at large) that their relationships with each other are ethically constrained and are bound by certain correlative duties.
What a consideration of the difficulties outlined above warn, however, is that if a human rights approach to mental health care ethics is to be taken, nurses need to be well informed about the pitfalls of this approach and understand that it may not always be helpful in guiding ethical professional conduct.

P sychiatric advance directives (‘Ulysses contracts’) in mental health

An integral and controversial component of psychiatric practice is involuntary care and treatment (Amering et al 1999). Although practised under the rubric of benevolent paternalism, the tenets of involuntary treatment have nonetheless seriously challenged and, in many instances, grossly violated the right of mentally ill persons — particularly those whose decision-making capacity has been seriously compromised by their illness — to make informed and self-determining choices about their care and treatment. Thus, the right to make informed and self-determining choices has the distinction of sparking sharp controversy in the field — a controversy that has been classically described as:
the apparent clash between two highly revered values: the ‘right to be let alone’ and the patient’s interest in the full and effective exercise of medical [sic] professionals’ healing skills.
(Dresser 1982: 777)
On account of the tension between patient autonomy and therapeutic paternalism in psychiatric contexts — and the extraordinarily difficult and sometime tragic situation this has often placed people in (consumers and caregivers alike) — advocates and commentators have searched for ways to reconcile or at least accommodate the opposing values at issue (Dresser 1982). A major outcome of this search has been the development and operationalisation in some jurisdictions of ‘psychiatric advanced directives’ (PADs) (also called ‘Ulysses contracts’, ‘Ulysses directives’ ‘psychiatric wills’, ‘pre-commitment directives’) (Lavin 1986; Spellecy 2003; Szasz 1982; Willigenburg & Delaere 2005). Although of pertinence and practical importance to improving the rights of mental health patients, there has been curiously little attention given to PADs in the Australian health professional, health law, or bioethics literature. It is to providing a brief overview of the possible role of PADs in mental health care that this discussion now turns.

S triking a balance between promoting autonomy and preventing harm

People with serious mental illnesses can often experience periods of profound distress during which their capacity to make prudent and rationally competent choices concerning their care and treatment options can be seriously compromised. During such periods, the mentally ill can also be at serious risk of harming themselves and/or others. In either case, timely and effective psychiatric treatment and care is imperative.
In many instances, people with serious mental illnesses might not comply with and might even refuse altogether to accept recommended psychiatric treatment (e.g. oral or intramuscular psychotropic medication, or electroconvulsive therapy). In such instances, because of the psychiatric imperatives to treat their conditions (particularly if extremely distressed and ‘out of control’), the mentally ill are vulnerable to having medical treatments paternalistically imposed on them against their will. Enforced treatments, in such cases may, however, compound their distress and make future treatment difficult, especially if the patient later feels (i.e. during a moment of restored competency to decide) that the fiduciary nature of the professional–client relationship has been violated.
Situations involving the enforced medical treatment of the mentally ill can cause significant distress to caregivers as well who, while wanting to respect the choices of their patients, may nevertheless recognise that without treatment, patients in distress (and their families or supporters) will not be able to be consoled and, worse, may remain unnecessarily in a state of psychiatric crisis. Here very practical questions arise of what, if anything, can be done to strike a balance between respecting the patient’s autonomous wishes and constraining their freedom where its exercise could be harmful to themselves and/or to others?
For many, the answer lies in the systematic development and formal adoption of psychiatric advanced directives. Widdershoven and Berghmans (2001: 92) explain that:
By using psychiatric advance directives, it would be possible for mentally ill persons who are competent and with their disease in remission, and who want timely intervention in case of future mental crisis, to give prior authorisation to treatment at a later time when they are incompetent, non-compliant, and refusing treatment.
But what are PADs? And are they capable of achieving the outcomes that their proponents anticipate and expect?

H istorical overview of the development of psychiatric advance directives (PADs)

Psychiatric advance directives (PADs) are a relatively recent initiative that are based on the idea of ‘psychiatric wills’ (a term that is analogous to ‘living wills’). The idea of a psychiatric will is credited with originating in the work of the controversial American psychiatrist, Thomas Szasz (1982), and the need for psychiatric patients to have an instrument that enabled them to refuse unwanted treatment (Amering et al 1999; Cuca 1993; Srebnik & Brodoff 2003). The origin of the related idea and term ‘Ulysses contract’ is less clear although, coincidentally, it too is thought to date back to 1982, when it appeared in the title of a case study report published in the Hastings Center Report (1982a) (Cuca 1993: 1163).
‘Ulysses contracts’ (generally regarded as providing the model for PADs today) (see Atkinson 2004) derives from Homer’s story of the mythological character Ulysses (known as Odysseus in Greek mythology) who escaped being seduced to his death by the ‘sweet songs’ of the Sirens, the magical women of Cyrene, who cast spells on the sailors of ships so that their vessels would be wrecked and subsequently could be scavenged. Being previously warned of the evil intentions of the Sirens, Ulysses took the precaution of commanding his sailors to bind him to the mast of his ship (effectively restraining him), and to plug their ears with wax so that they could not hear and hence be seduced to their deaths by the Sirens. Ulysses further ordered his sailors not to release him from the mast until they were safely past the Sirens. By taking these steps, Ulysses was able to investigate the power of the Sirens without being seduced to his death by them as well as ensure the safety of his ship and his crew as they sailed past them. This story is used controversially in philosophy to demonstrate the difference between freedom and autonomy: in this case, although Ulysses had his freedom constrained (i.e. by having his body tied to the mast of his ship), his autonomy (rational preference) was essentially left intact — including during the momentary period of his incompetence while under the bewitching spell of the magical Sirens.
Contemporary models of PADs today can take one or both of two forms, notably:
▪ an instructional directive ‘that provides specific information about a patient’s treatment preferences’; and
▪ a proxy directive, in which a patient ‘appoints a surrogate decision-maker who has legal authority to make treatment decisions on behalf of the patient when incapacitated’ (Srebnik 2005: S42).
Depending on the legal regulations governing a given PAD, a directive can contain provisions for either ‘opting-out’ (refusing) treatment (both general and specific — e.g. ECT), or ‘opting-in’ (consenting to services as well as to specific treatments) (Atkinson et al 2003).

A nticipated benefits of PADs

PADs have been touted as having the capacity to realise a number of benefits, including ‘decrease hospitalizations, reduce coercion in treatment, and improve relationships between consumers, families and clinicians’ (Peto et al 2004); and destigmatising patients with mental illness on account of giving them the same rights to refuse psychiatric treatment as patients who wish to refuse general medical treatment (Atkinson et al 2004). To date, however, the anticipated benefits of PADs have yet to be realised. One reason for this is the systemic barriers to their use including a ‘lack of resources deployed to assist patients in preparing PADs, and lack of “buy-in” and acceptance of PADs by clinicians’ (Swanson et al 2007: 78). Lack of awareness and education about PADs (on the part of consumers and clinicians alike) has also been identified as a contributing factor (Peto et al 2004).
Despite this reticence, the PAD is increasingly being regarded as an important instrument that enables respect not only of the patient’s wishes, but also their values (i.e. in regard to what is important in life). And while PAD instruments should not ‘replace deliberation about possible future changes in the patients’ condition,’ they are nonetheless seen as having an important role to play in eliciting and guiding communication about such matters (Widdershoven & Berghmans 2001: 93; see also Spellecy 2003).

A nticipated risks of PADs

PADs are not without risk, however. Some commentators are especially worried about the moral authority of psychiatric advance directives (particularly if patients change their minds at some point), and their vulnerability to being abused and misused (Spellecy 2003). As Dresser (1982: 842) cautioned over two decades ago, if insufficiently informed persons enter into commitment contracts ‘only to please their psychiatrists, the contracts would become an avenue for the abuse of psychiatric paternalism, thus decreasing individual liberty’. Dresser further cautions that, in the absence of an opportunity for patients to withdraw consent to treatment, PADs in reality could well stand as a ‘coercive treatment mode that would take us a step backward — or at least sideways — from a more sensitive and realistic solution to a very difficult situation (Dresser 1982: 854).The inability to get ‘quick determinations’ of illness and competency — and hence healing treatment — has also been identified as a risk that could serve ultimately to undermine the effectiveness of PADs (Cuca 1993: 1178).
Like their counterparts advanced directives at the end stage of life (discussed in Chapter 12 of this book), however, PADs are amenable to a range of processes that can ensure they achieve their intended purpose; namely, ensuring protection of the patient’s significant moral interests, welfare and wellbeing. For example, during ‘critically reflective periods’ or ‘cool thinking periods’ the opportunity to revoke a previously made psychiatric advanced directive must always be present; treatment options should remain the subject of ongoing critical evaluation, and so on.
Earlier, in Chapter 6 of this book, under the discussion of competency to decide, the case was given of an involuntary psychiatric patient who was held down and given an intramuscular injection of psychotropic medication against his will (see pages 160–1). It will be recalled that this incident resulted in the patient being left highly mistrustful of nursing staff and even less willing to comply with his prescribed oral medication. There is room to speculate that had a PAD been in force at the time for this patient, a very different outcome might have resulted in this case.

C urrent trends in the legal regulation of PADs

The enactment of formal legislation regulating PADs is relatively new. The United States (US) has the longest history of PADs, with Minnesota in 1991 becoming the first American State to enact legislation giving recognition to the ‘advance psychiatric directive’ allowing its citizens to ‘draft directives for intrusive mental health treatments’ (Cuca 1993: 1165). Currently there are 21 states in the US that have legal processes in place for allowing and managing PADs (Atkinson et al 2003; Swartz et al 2006). These developments are regarded by some US researchers as being ‘one of the most significant developments in US mental health law and policy in recent years’ (Swanson et al 2007: 77).
Although early proponents of PADs in the US expected that their use would spread (Appelbaum 1991), this has not happened (Varekamp 2004). Only a few countries (e.g. Austria, Germany, Canada, Switzerland, the Netherlands and the United Kingdom (UK) have introduced or are working to introduce and uphold PADs or ‘Psychiatric wills’ (Amering et al 1999; Atkinson et al 2003; Varekamp 2004). In the UK, for example, the passage through parliament of the Mental Capacity Bill 2004–2005 (given Royal Assent in 2005, and coming into force in 2007) authorised a limited form of PADs (i.e. instruments provided for by this legislation can only be used to refuse, rather than give consent to treatment) (Meredith 2005: 9; Swartz et al 2006).
In Australia, although there is legal regulation (via legislation and case law) of advance directives, a firm distinction is made between psychiatric and non-psychiatric contexts in which advanced directives can be applied (Leo 2004). The effect of this is that advance directives legislation allows competent people to refuse proposed medical interventions for physical illness, but does not give the same effect to refusals made by competent people for psychiatric treatment (Foukas 1999; Leo 2004). Moreover, legislation still allows and authorises psychiatrists to override the consent of a patient in a psychiatric context ‘effectively renouncing the patient’s right to self-determination’ (Leo 2004: 5).
Despite strong advocacy by consumer groups and individuals in Australia (see Mental Health Legal Centre Inc 2004; PsychRights 2007; Strong, nd), there is no immediate indication that, with the notable exception of Queensland, Australia intends to go down the path of adopting PADs as a legal mechanism for promoting and protecting the rights of mentally ill people to participate effectively in decision-making concerning their psychiatric care and treatment. While acknowledging the limits of PADs, as one consumer advocate has pleaded:
Psychiatric Advance Directives can fulfil a real need — almost everyone I talk with about them immediately recognises that […] I’d like to see Psychiatric Advance Directives legally enforceable throughout Australia […] At the very least, I’d like to see changes to mental health legislation, removing any impediments to the use of Advance Directives in mental health settings. That said — I think Advance Directives can be used effectively, even in states where they have no formal legal status.
(Strong, nd)

T he moral responsibilities of nurses in mental health care

It has long been acknowledged that nurses are at the forefront of providing care to people suffering from mental illness, mental health disorders and other mental health-related problems (Burdekin et al 1993: 175–8). It is to be expected that in the course of caring for people with mental health problems, nurses will encounter a variety of practical ethical issues. These issues will vary both in kind and complexity, depending on:
▪ who the patient (client) is (e.g. whether the ‘patient’ is an individual, a family, a group or an entire community)
▪ where the patient is located (e.g. whether in a community or institutional setting, a private or public place, whether free or constrained physically, legally or otherwise)
▪ the cultural and language background of the patient and the availability of transcultural mental health services — including qualified mental health interpreters (if required) (see Victorian Government 2006)
▪ what resources are available to assist the patient in whatever form these resources might be required (e.g. a patient might be in need of legal aid and accommodation, not merely health care; a patient might also just be in need of ‘a friend’ — someone who will just sit and listen and reassure them that ‘everything will be OK’).
These considerations will, in turn, have a bearing on determining the nature of a nurse’s given moral responsibilities and the extent to which he or she is obligated to fulfil these.
For instance, it is quite probable that a nurse’s responsibilities do not just begin and end with an individual patient. If the whole notion of moral obligation is taken seriously from a professional point of view, then there is considerable room to suggest that the moral responsibilities of nurses extend far beyond their immediate one-to-one professional–client relationships to include other things such as professional and political activism aimed at improving the plight of those who suffer from mental health problems (Johnstone 2008, 2002b, 2001). Activism of this kind could be aimed at securing such things as: the demystification and destigmatisation of mental health disorders, mental illness and other mental health problems, better mental health care services (to be distinguished here from psychiatric services) for the community, and other general mechanisms which will assist those with mental health problems to be spared the devastating consequences of stigma and discrimination which many continue to suffer.
Given the above, it can be seen that practical ethical issues for mental health nurses can and do involve much more than the commonly discussed moral problems of the right to health care, informed consent and competency to decide, privacy and confidentiality, the political abuse of psychiatry and psychiatric research (see, e.g. Beauchamp & Childress 2001; Buchanan & Brock 1989; Chodoff et al 1999; Christensen 1997; Engelhardt 1996; Rave & Larsen 1995; Weinstein 1990). Other important practical issues concern the moral imperatives of the professional–client relationship (including mutuality, therapeutic alliance, safety, security, trust, compassion and empathy); the moral dimensions and unacceptable consequences of stigma and discrimination; and the moral imperatives of transcultural and Indigenous mental health nursing, to name some. Unfortunately, due to the limited scope of this discussion, it is not possible to explore all these issues in a manner that would do justice to them or which would provide nurses working in the mental health care sector with the in-depth understanding they need in order to be able to deal with these issues effectively. Nevertheless, they are identified here to alert nurses to the possible range of ethical issues they need to be informed about and which will, at some stage, have a bearing on their practice.

F uture directions in mental health care ethics

In recent years significant efforts have been made in Australia and elsewhere to redress the problem of human rights violations in mental health care settings, and to provide a framework for assuring the dignity and protection of the moral entitlements of people suffering from mental health problems. 2 However, it is evident that a great deal more needs to be done to improve the status quo. Certainly, initiatives aimed at educating the public, promoting mental health through mainstream health promotion activities, establishing preventative mental health programs as an essential component of care provision to people at risk of mental health problems, and promoting research, are all essential to promoting better ‘mental health outcomes’. If, however, there is to be a genuine promotion and realisation of ‘social justice, equity, access and a compassionate society with mental health as a primary goal’ (Raphael 1995), what is also required is the development, promotion and practice of a substantive mental health care ethic which recognises, among other things, that mental health is a ‘multi-dimensional, dynamic and interactive phenomenon’ (Tippett et al 1994: xii).
Earlier it was suggested that because of its widespread stigmatisation, mental illness is an illness that ‘strikes with a two-edged sword’ (Corrigan et al 2004). Many of the respondents to the 1993 Australian National Inquiry into the Human Rights of People with Mental Illness reaffirmed this, reporting that ‘one of the most debilitating aspects of being mentally ill was not the illness itself, but the social stigma it attracts’ (Burdekin et al 1993: 443). More telling, however, was the inquiry’s overall finding that what clients of mental health services were largely affected by were not the ‘big’ ethical issues such as those constructed as being ‘paramount’ by mainstream bioethics (e.g. informed consent, confidentiality, and so forth). Rather, clients were affected by much more ‘basic’ day-to-day relationship and existential issues which, while perhaps lacking the intrigue of other exotic bioethical issues, nevertheless have a profound moral dimension and warrant just as much attention as do the ‘big’ ethical issues which have tended to preoccupy contemporary mainstream bioethics discourse. The key issues identified by people with mental health problems were:
▪ the desperate need for understanding
▪ the need to be able to speak openly and to be heard
▪ the longing for acceptance by others of the mystery and the unpredictability of their illness, without constantly having to defend and explain to those who have little interest in understanding
▪ the desire to be equal with others and to have basic human rights respected.
(adapted from Burdekin et al 1993: 439–40)
Although the Burdekin report dates back to 1993, as the more recent literature cited in this chapter demonstrates, its findings remain current (see WHO 2001a).
What, then, are some of the lessons to be gained from these findings and what are their implications for the future development of mental health care ethics?
It has been claimed in this chapter that: if there is to be a genuine promotion and realisation of ‘social justice, equity, access and a compassionate society with mental health as a primary goal’ (Raphael 1995), what is also required is the development, promotion and practice of a substantive mental health care ethic. It remains to be said that such an ethic must, by its very nature, be one which is responsive to and reflective of the lived experiences of clients with mental health problems, as well as their carers. To achieve this, the development of such an ethic must begin not so much with the abstract theories and principles of traditional Western moral philosophy. Rather, such an ethic must take as its methodological starting point the lived realities and experiences of those who suffer as a result of their mental health problems as well as the lived realities and experiences of the people who share the primary responsibility of caring for them. Such an approach will also empower those whose lives have been affected by mental health problems to ‘speak for themselves’ and in so doing to challenge the status quo by virtue of engaging in the positive political act of ‘making visible’ their experiences and naming their own reality. ‘Speaking for themselves’ will also enable survivors of mental health problems to provide the foundations needed for achieving the understanding and respect they are so desperately seeking. Finally, such an approach will facilitate the development of our moral thinking generally and will enable a very ‘life-rich’ contribution to be made to mainstream bioethics discourse which remains largely incomplete because of the many ‘moral voices and moral selves’ (adapted from Hekman 1995) that have not yet been heard (see also the graphic ‘life stories’ presented in Glass 1989; Read & Reynolds 1996).

C onclusion

By virtue of their primary position as providers of mental health care, nurses have a fundamental role to play in promoting access, equity, compassion and social justice in mental health domains. This includes also being ‘sufficiently engaged in fighting stigma and discrimination related to mental illness’ (Sartorius 2002: 1471). Many of the topics covered in this text will assist nurses to develop a requisite understanding of the ethical issues they face when fulfilling their role and responsibilities as carers of people with mental health problems. Further assistance will be provided from the new and important work that is currently being undertaken in the discipline and which heralds a whole new understanding, acceptance, commitment and approach to mental health care ethics (psychiatric ethic) and to the people with mental health problems who stand most in need of the benefits of this work (see Hughes & Fulford 2005). Whether this work will succeed, however, will depend on the ‘right attitude’ of people. It will also depend on how successful stakeholders in mental health discourses are in demystifying mental health disorders, mental illness and other mental health-related problems, and stripping the stigmatisation from these issues that historically has seen them relegated to the ‘too hard basket’, not just in mainstream ethics discourse, but in the minds of us all.
Case scenario 13

While driving one evening, a woman with an 8-year history of paranoid schizophrenia became so disturbed by racing thoughts and altered perceptions of external stimuli that she felt unsafe and abandoned her car in the middle of a busy road. From a nearby telephone booth, she rang a private psychiatric hospital in which she had previously been a patient and sought assistance. She explained to the nurse who received her call that she was ‘too frightened to drive’ in case she hurt other people, and she was afraid to go home in case her estranged husband (from whom she was being divorced) would have her committed as an involuntary patient at a local psychiatric facility. Unfortunately, the woman no longer had any health insurance and her only source of income was an invalid’s pension. Thus she could not be re-admitted to the private hospital where she had been treated previously. Concerned about the woman’s safety, the nurse who received the telephone call secured the assistance of a second nurse to keep the woman talking on the phone while arrangements for her safe removal from the telephone booth could be made. One hour later, the woman was finally ‘rescued’ from the telephone box. When she was found, she was observed to be ‘exhausted and sitting on the floor of the telephone booth in tears’. The reason it took so long to assist the woman was because the nurses involved encountered the following difficulties:
▪ when the local police were contacted for assistance, their initial response was that the woman ‘had already requested assistance in person’ and that she ‘was a “nutter” who wanted a free ride home’
▪ when the seriousness of the case was explained, the police responded by stating that they had no car available and that one would have to be dispatched via the Police Department’s Communication Centre (PDCC)
▪ minutes later the police called back to advise the nurse that the PDCC had refused to dispatch a car, stating it was the ambulance service’s responsibility to transport a psychiatric patient (the traffic hazard posed by the woman’s car was ignored)
▪ when contacted, the ambulance service responded appropriately and took the woman to the emergency department of a local hospital
▪ the hospital, however, refused admission to the woman on the grounds that she ‘did not live within the hospital’s region’
▪ it was recommended that the woman be subsequently transported to another facility — specifically the one she feared
▪ some days later it was revealed that the patient never arrived at the local psychiatric facility on the day in question (she had refused ambulance transport out of fear of the designated hospital and walked home because her car had been hit by moving traffic)
▪ later the woman was certified because of her ‘deteriorating mental state and erratic and dangerous behaviour’ and admitted to the very hospital she feared.
Case scenario 2

On 7 March 2003, Mark Patten, a 27-year-old electrician who had a long history of depression, suicided. It is reported that, on the night before Mr Patten’s death, his mother had tried to get him admitted, through the ambulance service, to hospital. Despite a psychiatrist also providing written advice to the hospital seeking the man’s admission (the psychiatrist deemed Mr Patten a ‘high suicide risk’ and needing in-patient care), a psychiatric triage nurse reportedly advised Mr Patten’s mother that ‘he was not on the critical list and she could not help her’ (Berry 2004: 2). It is also reported that the nurse further advised the mother ‘to give Mr Patten his medication and that she would report it to the crisis and treatment team, which would contact her the next day’ (p 2). Tragically, Mr Patten suicided early in the day before the crisis and treatment team had got to see him.

CRITICAL QUESTIONS

1. What were the patient’s rights in these situations?
2. What corresponding duties were owed to them and by whom?
3. If you were the nurse receiving the telephone calls in these cases, how would you have dealt with the situation?
4. What are your rights and responsibilities as a professional caregiver in regard to caring for people with mental health problems?
5. Is the nursing profession doing enough to advocate and promote the welfare and wellbeing of the mentally ill? If not, what can and should be done to improve the status quo?
Endnotes
1. The notions, ‘mental disorders’, ‘mental illness’, ‘psychiatric disorders’ and ‘mental health problem’ are not synonymous, and thus it would be misleading to use them interchangeably. For instance, a person can have a mental health problem yet not be ‘mentally disordered’.
In Australia, ‘mental disorder’ is a term used to ‘describe individuals suffering from some form of psychiatric condition which impairs their functioning’ (Tomison 1996: 2). Although the terms ‘mental disorder’ and ‘mental illness’ are often used synonymously, ‘mental illness’ is a form of legalese used in legal contexts to refer to persons considered ‘patients’ under various state and territory Mental Health Acts. In contrast, persons suffering from a ‘psychiatric condition’ are defined as ‘those who have a mental disorder that has had a disabling effect on them’ (Tomison 1996: 2). Controversially, a mental health problem, in turn, could be distinguished as a ‘problem’ of a psychogenic sort which causes discomfort — and even a certain degree of distress, but does not interfere with the sufferer’s functioning and performance of social responsibilities.
2. See, in particular, the National Mental Health Policy (Australian Health Ministers 1995); the Mental Health Statement of Rights and Responsibilities (Mental Health Consumer Outcomes Task Force 1995); the Evaluation of the National Mental Health Strategy: Final Report (National Mental Health Strategy Evaluation Steering Committee 1997); ‘Out of hospital, out of mind!’: A Review of Mental Health Services in Australia — 2003 (Groom & Hickie 2003); The World Health Report 2001, Mental Health: New Understanding, New Hope (WHO 2001a); and other reports available via the Mental Health Council of Australia [at www.mhca.com.au/] and the Australian Commonwealth Department of Health and Ageing [at www.mentalhealth.gov.au/].
3. Taken from Johnstone M (2001) ‘Stigma, social justice and the rights of the mentally ill: challenging the status quo’, Australian and New Zealand Journal of Mental Health Nursing, 10: 200–9.