Screening for adult disease

Published on 11/04/2015 by admin

Filed under Surgery

Last modified 11/04/2015

Print this page

rate 1 star rate 2 star rate 3 star rate 4 star rate 5 star
Your rating: none, Average: 0 (0 votes)

This article have been viewed 1046 times

6

Screening for adult disease

Principles of screening

Introduction

Medical screening is a public health activity that involves examining or testing asymptomatic, apparently healthy people to detect disease at an early stage. Measures can then be taken to prevent the disease (if there is a precursor stage), treat it early (hoping for improved cure rates), or at least offer treatment to delay advanced disease. For example, colonic screening can detect adenomas and carcinomas; removing adenomas prevents the well-recognised adenoma–carcinoma sequence, and actual cancers detected are often earlier and at a more curable stage. Unfortunately, for cancers without an easily detected early precursor stage such as breast or prostate, beneficial outcomes are elusive.

Screening can detect disorders that predispose to other diseases, for example, hypertension or elevated cholesterol levels, to discover people at increased risk of atherosclerotic heart disease and stroke. Screening is also useful for infection control, e.g. preoperative screening of patients from residential homes for meticillin-resistant Staphylococcus aureus (MRSA) carrier status to enable elimination therapy before operation.

An entire population can be screened (mass screening) but more usually it is targeted at at-risk groups. Selection might be by age, gender or cardiovascular risk factors, for example (Box 6.1). Opportunistic screening involves a more random approach, such as screening patients who happen to attend a particular clinic.

Assessing the potential benefits of screening

Many subscribe to the simplistic view that screening must be ‘a good thing’. These include the lay public, people associated with distressing diseases, populist politicians and people with vested financial interests. Poorly conceived screening, however, may consume massive resources to identify just a few new cases with little clinical benefit, e.g. CT scanning for lung cancer. Worse still, early diagnosis of a condition where early intervention brings no advantage may cause suffering. These people can be prematurely placed into an anxiety-provoking sick role and given unrealistic expectations. They may also be subjected to unnecessary treatments with potentially severe side-effects, e.g. some breast or prostate cancers that might never progress to invasive disease.

As with any public health measure, medical and social benefits accruing from any screening programme need to be rigorously evaluated and the process separated entirely from the incentive to screen for profit. Whole-body scanning by CT or MRI is currently strongly marketed on the basis that a scan will show unsuspected abnormalities and allow early treatment. Abnormalities are bound to be discovered by such extensive screening, but it is difficult to reliably determine which signify serious disease and which (if any) should be treated. Doctors should not perform unvalidated screening tests any more than they should use unproven drugs, and should resist patient pressure for inappropriate screening.

Premature introduction of screening: Politicians can play a part in initiating inappropriate screening programmes. UK prime minister, Margaret Thatcher sanctioned nationwide breast screening in 1988, 2 weeks before a general election; some believe this was to garner the women’s vote. The decision was premature and based on insufficiently validated evidence from the Swedish two counties study and the UK Forrest report. In the 1970s, screening for cancer of the uterine cervix was widely introduced, also before its efficacy had been fully evaluated. Fortunately, it has proved successful despite the difficulty of engaging women at high risk. Sadly, the natural history of untreated dysplastic cervical cellular abnormalities was not properly established before the impact of widespread screening made this ethically impossible. This severely hampered scientific study of the disease, its early diagnosis and best treatment.

Criteria for assessing a screening programme: Many years ago the World Health Organization (WHO) realised that even beneficial screening could be expensive, unpleasant, inaccurate and unproductive, and could adversely affect psychological or physical well-being. In 1968, they published a list of criteria for effective screening programmes (Box 6.2) including attributes of the disease, the test and the treatment. These principles are still relevant today and have been added to by the UK National Screening Committee and other groups. Box 6.3 shows a summary of these modified criteria.

Criteria for an effective screening programme

In order to initiate a new national screening programme, certain criteria must be fulfilled. There must be a perceived need in the medical community or in the wider public. Pilot studies are then carried out. If outcomes are promising, large scale prospective randomised controlled trials (RCTs) need to be performed, seeking robust evidence for implementation. This is critical because it is politically difficult to stop a screening programme, even when evidence shows little benefit, e.g. breast screening (Nordic Cochrane Collaboration 2001 and 2006).

The disease: The screened condition should be an important health problem either because it is common (such as lung or prostate cancer) or has serious but preventable consequences such as carotid artery disease or abdominal aortic aneurysm (AAA). The prevalence (proportion of cases already in a population) and the incidence (the proportion of new cases) of the disease in the population at risk are discovered from pilot studies. There should be a truly early stage where treatment outcomes are better than at a late stage. Colorectal adenomas and early cancers are good examples.

The biological behaviour or natural history of the disease should be well understood, including how latent disease progresses to clinical disease, and the disease course should be reasonably predictable. For example, AAAs are known to expand smoothly for the most part and rarely rupture until they are large. The risks of untreated disease also need to be understood and there should be a long period between the first detectable stages and overt disease.

The diagnostic test: The test must be valid, i.e. reliable in detecting the disease. This is defined by sensitivity and specificity. Sensitivity is the capability of the test to identify affected individuals in the screened population, i.e. the proportion of people who have the disease and are detected. A test with many false negative results is insensitive and unreliable. A UK appeal court ruled that sensitivity is paramount in (cervical) screening and awarded damages to women with missed diagnoses at screening. Specificity is the degree to which a positive test can be relied upon to prove the disease is present; in other words, the higher the false positive rate, the lower the specificity.

The test must be simple and cheap and it must identify the disease by a reliable, validated and reproducible method. The distribution of test values should be understood well enough to define normality or relative risk associated with particular stages, e.g. for an AAA, the diameter with a high risk of rupture. Intervals for repeating the test should be worked out for normal subjects and for those with positive results near the threshold.

The complete screening programme must be clinically safe and acceptable socially and ethically to health professionals and the public. This includes the test and any diagnostic procedures, treatments or interventions screening initiates. For example, if a test is perceived as unpleasant, e.g. colonoscopy, uptake is low and the benefits are proportionately smaller.

The overall benefits should be greater than the risks; this includes any physical and psychological harm caused by the test, diagnostic procedures and treatment.