Chapter 13. Involving communities in decision making
Gavin Mooney
Introduction
Ultimately, it is for patients that we seek to improve the management of clinical processes. In recent years, the place of patients and consumers of healthcare has shifted. The view of patients as passive receivers of healthcare is being replaced by one of communities as equal partners in decision making about healthcare priorities, contributing their opinions alongside those of bureaucrats and policymakers. Through ‘deliberative democracy’, this involvement takes a number of forms, such as citizens’ juries in which the UK is leading the way (Bristol Primary Health and Social Care 2006, McIver 1998). As a process, deliberative democracy is being used in different ways and for different purposes. In this respect, the chapter discusses the issue of community governance and distinguishes different levels of community involvement: in decision making, principles setting and being consulted. It briefly outlines the historical context of community participation in health and the values and benefits of community participation in setting principles and priority setting.
The chapter examines the principles, purposes and advantages of bringing ‘the community’ more into decision making in healthcare, especially where the question arises of whose values are to be used. The principles on which deliberative democracy might be built are many but foremost are issues of democracy and social justice. The chapter goes on to address the question of what sorts of issues around decision making it is appropriate to bring community values to bear. Deliberative democracy holds out a number of advantages, including greater readiness to comply with policy and hence boost policy effectiveness and efficiency. At a much broader level, it can help to build a greater sense of community and enhance social cohesion.
While different processes exist for eliciting preferences from communities when decisions are being made, in this chapter citizens’ juries are proposed as often the best way forward. Citizens’ juries bring a random selection of citizens together, give them good information and a chance to quiz experts and thereafter discuss and reflect on certain questions about healthcare, against a background of resource constraints. An Australian example of a citizens’ jury is presented and advanced as one that could be replicated to good purpose elsewhere. The way citizens’ juries can be used to aid in setting priorities is outlined.
The chapter concludes by summarising the outcomes of community participation, the advantages it brings and how to manage the plurality of interests and grapple with balancing power in decision making. Finally, the impact of these outcomes is discussed as service objectives and priorities are reconsidered.
Background to community involvement
This section examines the principles, purposes and advantages in bringing ‘the community’ more into decision making in healthcare, especially regarding the question of the values to be used in healthcare planning and priority setting.
What constitutes community is clearly crucial to this discussion, and it is unfortunate that the concept is not agreed in the literature. The community is not ‘all things to all people’; rather the existence of many different communities needs to be acknowledged. Boswell (1990:5) argues that the exploration of what is meant by community is ‘hindered not by the complete absence of community ideas but by their pervasiveness. In fact, they are all around us but in immature, secondary or emasculated forms. This produces a widespread illusion that they are alive and well, and do not need intellectual effort’. Generally, communities are conceived of as geographically located. This represents the most common usage and the most long-standing usage historically. There are however various other possibilities. Prominent among these are social groupings that can be ethnically, religiously, sports or recreationally based.
In the context of economics, and possibly of other concerns, the issue that separates those who seek more emphasis on community and those of a more individualistic bent (most liberals and certainly neoliberals) is the nature and importance of choice. Bell (2004) argues that the former cast doubt ‘on the view that choice is intrinsically valuable, that a certain moral principle or communal attachment is more valuable simply because it has been chosen following deliberation among alternatives by an individual subject’. Bell makes the further point that ‘the valorization of greed in the Thatcher/Reagan era justified the extension of instrumental considerations governing relationships in the marketplace into spheres previously informed by a sense of uncalculated reciprocity and civil obligation’, that is, what are in essence features of a strong community. Health and healthcare are included in these spheres, which were not previously, but now are often seen as able to be governed by the forces of the marketplace. There has been a move to ‘commodify’ healthcare in the past 20 years or so, with increasing tendencies to see it as a market good. This has been accompanied by a willingness to consider privatisation as the way to deliver healthcare well, where ‘well’ is seen in terms of market efficiency with equity disappearing from view. It would be an exaggeration to suggest that health has become a private good (it is not a good at all if that is defined as something that is capable of being traded); nonetheless the way that health is being seen in public policy places it more at the door of individual responsibility.
Individualism increasingly dominates even within public health services, for example in the measurement of health. Further, the language of the market and market-based managerialism is becoming more pervasive: public healthcare has ‘providers’, ‘consumers’ and ‘business plans’. As the ethos of the MBA takes over, health services as social and community institutions succumb to quantification through performance indicators and worshipping at the altar of QEBM (quantified evidence-based medicine) (Mooney 2004). The notion of a community ‘caring about’ (Little 2000) its members and caring about community health is lost; not because it is absent, but because it is not measurable.
In this chapter, two important issues differentiate a community focus from the individualism of marketplace liberalism. The former allows for, indeed encourages, the inclusion of intangibles such as compassion and cultural diversity, and is more likely to encapsulate the value of process as well as outcomes. Conversely, the individualism of liberalism is concerned with consequences, that is, what is measurable at an individual level, and makes claims to be universal. Marketplace liberalism and certainly neoliberalism are concerned with freedom of choice, with the emphasis on individual choice. An added assumption is that individuals are willing, and able, to exercise consumer sovereignty, indeed that there is a moral goodness about individual choice. This strand can be further split into two parts: the first being about choice per se, and the notion, through choice, of ‘revealed preferences’, that is, that studying individuals’ choices in the marketplace allows us to judge what their preferences and strengths of preferences are; and the second, the fact that this choice is individual choice.
To what extent, though, can choice be only individual when goods are held in common? As Taylor (1989) writes
The crucial point … is this: since the free individual can only maintain his identity within a society/culture of a certain kind, he has to be concerned about the shape of this society/culture as a whole. He cannot … be concerned purely with his individual choices and the associations formed from such choices to the neglect of the matrix in which such choices can be open or closed, rich or meagre. It is important to him that certain activities and institutions flourish in society. It is even of importance to him what the moral tone of the whole society is … because freedom and individual diversity can only flourish in a society where there is a general recognition of their worth.
If realizing our freedom partly depends on the society and culture in which we live, then we exercise a fuller freedom if we can help determine the shape of this society and culture.
There is much to discuss in adopting a community perspective of choice and decision making. There are social aspects that a marketeer will choose to ignore or play down. The concepts of freedom are different, especially in the neoliberalism of the marketplace. Oddly, as Taylor hints, freedom is not consciously and overtly valued in the marketplace in the sense that it is not seen as being in need of protection. Rather it is taken for granted, as a given. The market delivers freedom. This is close to being a mantra: a fundamental belief, and as with most fundamental beliefs not open to question – not even subject to question. In a fully fledged market one individual freely exchanges with another individual and they only freely choose to do so if they both believe that they will thereby be better off. The case is proven!
The shaping of the economy follows from this two-person exchange, as the whole economy can be seen as simply a large number of such two-person exchanges all entered into freely. In recent years in the wake of inter alia Thatcher’s famous statement that there is no such thing as a society, the economy and society have become – in neoliberal speech – synonymous, and the word citizen is obsolete as the consumer becomes all that individuals are seen to be. The shaping of society for those who still believe in such an entity can in turn be left to the market and individuals do not have to be concerned about it.
Emphasising community does three things. First, it shifts concern to the shaping of society and a belief that issues around health and healthcare cannot be left to individuals qua individuals. It is citizens as moulded by the society or the community who shape, and, importantly, are shaped by, the society or community. Here, community identity and individual identity are interlocked and interdependent. The distinction between citizen and consumer thus becomes critical. The distinction is well made by McPherson (1977) who claims that
[o]ne can acquire and consume oneself, for one’s own satisfaction or to show one’s superiority to others … whereas the enjoyment and development of one’s capacities is to be done for the most part in conjunction with others, in some relation of community. And it will not be doubted that the operation of participatory democracy would require a stronger sense of community than now prevails.
Boswell (1990) makes a separate but related point regarding the distinction between citizens and consumers.
The participatory democracy model has been sharply contrasted with the view which sees democracy primarily as an output mechanism, a begetter of wealth and economic growth. It has been said that this latter concept essentially views human beings as infinite consumers and accumulators … whereas under the participatory model we are to regard ourselves primarily as exerters and enjoyers of our capacities.
(Boswell 1990:31)
Second, it is based on the assumption that community preferences will not equate with the summation of individuals’ preferences. There are contexts in which individual votes cast in secret can be the way to reach decisions for the group or community, but having people debating and reflecting as a community on issues can come up with different answers and in some instances may be a preferable way of reaching decisions. Third, it brings out as important the idea of establishing what may be best described as the social good of healthcare. This might be simply in terms of ‘outcomes’ such as health, or perhaps through the ‘capabilities’ of Sen (1992); such capabilities being about freedoms to be or to act: in essence, freedoms to function.
Anderson (1993) argues at a general level that democratic institutions allow people to live in the sorts of social conditions where they have the autonomy to express and live their own values in ways with which they are happy. She is derisive of the idea of commodity fetishism where all that is valued by people is available in the marketplace. What is needed, she suggests, is to create institutions where people have voice directly and do not have to operate through so called experts. The same argument can be used more specifically for healthcare consumption and for health in general. Anderson’s ‘institutions of voice’ are particularly important in healthcare if the healthcare system is seen as a social institution. There is very clearly a need for agency – the expert doctor assisting the ill-informed patient – at the level of the doctor–patient relationship. There is a tendency however for this issue to have a spillover effect when it comes to health services as systems. Doctors can become embroiled in discussions about the healthcare system as a system: whether it is adequately funded, what the priorities ought to be in terms of diseases or types of beds, lengths of waiting lists, and so on. Such involvement is not necessarily problematic in itself, but it is too often conducted in terms that suggest doctors are experts at these levels. They are not.
Joan Robinson (1972) makes the point that
‘[n]o-one who has lived in the capitalist world is deceived by the pretence that the market system ensures consumer’s sovereignty’. She continues: ‘The true moral to be drawn from capitalist experience is that production will never be responsive to consumer needs as long as the initiative lies with the producer… In a planned economy the best hope seems to be to develop a class of functionaries, playing the role of wholesale dealers, whose career and self-respect depend upon satisfying the consumer. They could keep in touch with demand through the shops; market research which in the capitalist world is directed to finding out how to bamboozle the housewife could be directed to discovering what she really needs; design and quality could be imposed upon manufacturing enterprises and the product mix settled by placing orders in such a way as to hold a balance between economies of scale and variety of tastes.
(Robinson 1972:274)
The parallels with healthcare are very real. Consumer sovereignty does not exist in healthcare and we can go further and argue that consumers do not want it to exist. It is not, as the standard health economics literature implies with agency, that the agent is there to assist the consumer to make decisions that he or she would make in the market if as well informed as the agent. This role cannot be played by the doctor. We need another type of ‘functionary’ as Robinson suggests (see above) ‘whose career and self-respect depend upon satisfying’ not the consumer but the patient. We have par excellence in healthcare a situation where ‘production will never be responsive to consumer needs as long as the initiative lies with the producer’.
The healthcare sector needs to be responsive not to consumer needs per se but to community needs and preferences. The patient is often heavily dependent on the doctor to act in the role of his or her agent. There is information asymmetry between them. That is accepted by both sides. It is the main reason why we train doctors to such high levels and a reason why we ask them to abide by ethical codes of conduct. It would be grossly inefficient for patients to chase information themselves. Nonetheless, there is an unfortunate tendency to assume that the citizen suffers from information asymmetry in respect of decision making in healthcare and that he or she is willing to hand over decision making at this level to managers and senior doctors. In some instances they may, but they need to be asked, and when the doctors and managers are not willing, there need to be mechanisms available to allow citizens to be involved. This is where deliberative democracy comes into play.
Why bother with deliberative democracy?
There is a lengthy history of seeking to involve citizens or the community in health service decision making. In 1954, the World Health Organization (1954) argued for such a shift to embrace citizens’ values in health service decision making. Such a move has been frequently endorsed since then (Vuori 1984), most recently by the Romanow Commission in Canada (Romanow 2002). Regardless, Australian governments have been slow to engage citizens in healthcare decision making.
To some extent the expectations of participation depend on the context in which it is set. At its most fundamental, there are two, perhaps three, overarching objectives in healthcare. The simplest is to make the health service ‘better’; the second is to foster democracy and democratic governance; and, while furthering social cohesion and better social institutions is related to the second, it is given a separate heading here because of its potential importance. There are problems with ‘doing better’: What is meant by ‘better’ and how might such betterment be evaluated or measured? ‘Better’ is often interpreted as ‘more efficient’ (Abelson & Eyles 2002) and this objective is less likely to be achieved through technical efficiency than through allocative efficiency. The former is about doing better or doing more with the same resources. This is not something that citizens can be expected to get worked up about or to address with any degree of knowledge. It is a ‘technical’ matter. The public are likely to recognise that and to leave it to the technicians, that is, various healthcare professionals and managers.
Allocative efficiency is where the impact of community consultation is to be felt. It is about maximising benefit with the resources available – often described as ‘doing the right thing’. Abelson & Eyles (2002) argue that ‘public participation may potentially contribute to the effective performance of the health system by helping to create a fully informed citizenry, transparency and, ultimately, accountability, and in this way contribute to the achievement of efficiency goals’. By putting it in these terms Abelson & Eyles miss a key point. Allocative efficiency involves judgments about how best to use resources. This ‘best’ is value laden and switching from one group’s values (say healthcare managers’) to another’s (say citizens’) may well result in a different answer. There might be agreement between the managers and the citizens about the effectiveness of an intervention in, say, providing more care for the elderly living at home or about the effectiveness of another intervention for screening women younger than currently for Down syndrome, but how the two groups judge the relative value of the two effects may differ. This is a major part of what allocative efficiency is about; it is where citizens’ values may lead to a different allocation of resources.
It becomes obvious that trying to evaluate and measure any impact on allocative efficiency using citizens’ values is difficult. The role of the public official or bureaucrat in the absence of citizens’ values should not be to use his or her own values but to try to reflect the values of the community served. Thus, provided that any consultative process manages to elicit genuine community values – and assessing that is hard – then if the process results in some recommendation to alter the allocation of resources from that which the managers would have recommended, there has to be an improvement in allocative efficiency. Thus, in pursuing allocative efficiency, it is clearly better to use direct community values than public officials’ proxies for community values.
Fostering democracy and democratic governance is an accompanying issue. While perhaps instrumental, some writers (Kashefi & Mort 2004) argue for this as an outcome, consequence or benefit in its own right. Kashefi & Mort warn against some of the problems of settling for instrumentality. ‘Incidental’ consultations are deeply mistrusted and can be seen as ‘social control disguised as democratic emancipation’ or ‘simply … ways of deflecting criticisms of mainstream (un)democratic practice’ (Glasner 2001:44). These same authors express concern at ‘the heavy reliance by health and social care agencies on the extractive, incidental outputs of the consultation industry’. Certainly, there are risks associated with public consultation. It can result in a cynical response in attempting to build democratic governance, and this author has experienced such cynicism in facilitating citizens’ juries, albeit from a small minority of jurists. Most enthusiastically endorse the process and express positive feelings (even delight!) at being involved.
Despite the reservations of some observers (e.g. Abelson & Eyles 2002), the experience of this author (e.g. Mooney & Blackwell 2004, Mooney 2007) is that in asking people to put on their citizens’ hats and think and act and judge and express preferences as citizens about some big broad issues such as: What values should underpin your health service? They revel in doing so. Abelson & Eyles’ experience is clearly different; they feel more comfortable in getting citizens to pursue issues in which they have a self-interest. The differences are no doubt real. This author has encouraged citizens to be citizens of whatever jurisdiction was relevant, such as a citizen of the state of Western Australia and not of Perth or Geraldton or Kalgoorlie. Of course they bring their values to the table, but they seem able to be ‘state’ citizens rather than ‘town’ citizens, and most importantly, ‘citizens’ rather than ‘consumers’ or ‘patients’.
Building democratic governance into health services will never be easy. If it is to happen, it involves inter alia somebody somewhere giving up power: politicians or bureaucrats or senior doctors. If the process is to work, the group who must be won over is the politicians. Fortunately they are the least obstructive. They have something to gain by being seen to listen to the voice of the informed citizen. Bureaucrats and senior doctors lose power with no balancing factor. Related to this second point is the role of public participation in building new social institutions and in turn social coherence. (The latter may well be advantageous in the context of the social determinants of health but other than noting that and its potential importance, the point is not taken further here.) There are arguments (Muller 2003) for seeking to build new social institutions at this point in history. In Australia, for example, the recent past and especially the past decade has seen major erosion of some social institutions: the public service has become more politicised; there has been heavy political leaning on the public broadcaster; the independence of the judiciary has been threatened; the structure of the economy has become more neoliberal and the tax base has shrunk with a resultant move to market power and away from democratic government control; and globalisation has seen a shift of power to international organisations, such as the World Trade Organization, and to international controls at the expense of local democratic freedoms.
It would be foolish to suggest that threats to our freedom can be halted by organising a few public consultations on Australian healthcare. There is an argument, however, that to start a trend in that direction could be important. It makes a lot of sense to start the process in health, given the concerns that the public have regarding healthcare at any time, but especially now. There is an interest in the pursuit of social justice in this sector which is perhaps more telling and simply stronger than in many others.
Community consultation about what?
There are all sorts of issues in which and for which the involvement of citizens might come into play. Their involvement can be used for decision making at a national level down to some very local town or village locality. There is no strong argument for ruling out any of these levels in principle. Citizens do need to feel involved. Such feelings are perhaps stronger at a local level but in the author’s experience people in Western Australia have had no problem in acting as citizens at the state level. What is more open for debate is the locus of the decisions and the level or specifics of involvement (Mooney 2007).
Perhaps the best way to use citizens is to get them to inform the ethical base of health service decision making, providing – or as a minimum assisting in providing – the values or principles on which to base healthcare delivery. It might stop at this level and the example given below is about setting principles. How to decide what citizens should do or get involved in is not easy, but there are two key guides. First, the issues to be addressed by citizens must be ones in which they want to get involved. They need to be able to claim some ownership of them. If they do not, then they and those seeking their involvement may be wasting their time. Second, but closely related, the issues ought to be ones that citizens have some knowledge of or can obtain adequate knowledge of without too much effort. Citizens are not well placed to form judgments about which medicines to prescribe in particular circumstances for instance, and the chances are they will not want to anyway.
‘The legitimacy’ of whatever a community consultation comes up with also matters. There are two sides here: the citizens’ and the current decision makers’. First, citizens will be quick to be cynical about being consulted if they feel that they are out of their depth technically or they are being used as pawns or as a means to allow decision makers to put a tick in a box saying ‘community consulted’. Second, there will be many, particularly those who have the property rights, that is, the power over decision making currently, who will be willing to criticise anything that communities come up with: the matters are too complex for ordinary citizens; citizens really don’t want to be involved; these are technical matters; consulting the community is always flawed and biased; whoever leads the process will lead the citizens; and so on. Against this background, the question of legitimacy to decision makers inevitably looms large. Ensuring that citizens are randomly selected, that they are well informed and that they avoid wish-listing by having their preferences constrained within some limited resources helps to reduce criticism of the values they derive. Decision makers are more likely to accept community values if they are about broad value issues than if they get closer to the technical province of, say, medical matters. Such issues as equity, its definition and relative importance are ones that most would concede are the legitimate concern of the public.
Priority setting
The other issue that citizens might legitimately participate in, closely aligned with principles and values, is that of priority setting. Who should set priorities in healthcare remains an issue of debate. Whatever the flaws and problems in involving informed citizens in a priority setting approach, there is no better group to do so if these priorities are about more macro-level issues, such as choosing between different disease groups or between the health of different social or cultural groupings. For more technical matters, such as the mix of employment of different categories of staff, the role of citizens is likely to be less and in some instances minimal or zero. (See Iedema, Sorensen, Jorm & Piper, Chapter 7.)
What does priority setting involve? There are many different approaches to priority setting (Honigsbaum et al 1995) but the one most commonly advocated by economists is ‘program budgeting and marginal analysis’ that involves:
▪ giving a picture of what current spending goes to in terms of ‘programs’ such as client groups (e.g. care of the elderly, mental health, maternity care) or disease groups (cancer, heart, diabetes) or geographical or social groups
▪ then asking: if, say, $1 million were taken from care of the elderly and transferred to child care would the loss in benefit to the elderly be less than the gain for children? If the answer is yes, then efficiency tells us to make that shift. And then ask the same question with respect to another $1 million.
The idea here is straightforward and rational. Making such comparisons of these ‘marginal’ changes between programs, hence the name Program Budgeting and Marginal Analysis (PBMA), is difficult in practice since it can involve trading off very different forms of benefit – apples and oranges. But people do in reality trade off apples and oranges and as citizens they can do it in heathcare as well. Olsen & Donaldson (1998) asked a Norwegian community to choose between more hips, more hearts and a helicopter ambulance. The community were able to do so. Such a choice involves trading off quality of life with hips; quantity of life with hearts; and primarily equity with the helicopter ambulance.
Should citizens make choices such these? It is difficult to see who else could. In Australia, priority setting has largely been left to politicians and the Australian Medical Association (AMA). There is nothing ‘wrong’ with that, at least with respect to politicians. The question is: Can it be better? This is an ethical question. Much that democratically elected politicians decide has by its nature to be determined in some broad mandate at elections where health is considered in a package with education, foreign affairs, tax policy, and so on. Deliberative democracy at least allows something closer to ‘grass roots democracy’. It can also capture finer detail than is possible at elections, such as the principles that might underpin healthcare policy.
Another argument for involving citizens directly is that they can act as a countervailing power to bureaucrats and medical organisations such as the AMA in Australia. The former can and do influence policy using their own values, sometimes doing so explicitly, more often implicitly. Such a position is defended on the basis that otherwise there would be a values vacuum. The latter do so by powerful lobbying and they are not neutral. Countering pressure from medical associations is for governments and bureaucrats. One way of doing so is to be able to say: ‘Ah the people have spake and what they say is …’
Having found that the four citizens’ juries in WA with which the author has been involved have tended to support greater equity in resource allocation in the state health service (Mooney 2007), particularly Aboriginal health, the author has attempted to use this information in the media to influence public debate. Quoting the voice of the people is certainly more powerful than that of one academic health economist.
Citizens’ juries – an example
Public consultation comes in all sorts of shapes and sizes. Citizens’ juries are the main focus of discussion here; others are consensus conferences, deliberative polling, focus groups, public meetings and forums, and population surveys of various types. Citizens’ juries are preferred because:
▪ they are randomly selected
▪ they avoid the self-selection bias of many of the others
▪ the participants are directed to be and think as citizens
▪ they meet as a group which inter alia strengthens the community/citizen role
▪ they have time to reflect and deliberate as a group
▪ the information base they work with is common, or at least what they are presented with by experts
▪ they do not have to receive the information passively (they can question the experts and ask for additional information)
▪ they can be constrained in terms of the resources at their disposal in making their choices, which avoids wish-listing (which other forms of consultation can promote).
Following is an example of one particular citizens’ jury. The example is from Australia, although the principles and practice involved can be usefully applied elsewhere. This jury was held in Busselton, southwest Western Australia in October 2005 and was followed by, and the results used to inform, a public health forum that took place on the succeeding two days. That forum involved 260 people including members of the public who were not randomly selected, health service staff, healthcare consumers, local government staff and councillors and other community representatives. Their task was to look at more operational issues, but beyond mentioning that public forum, no more is made of it here.
Citizens’ jury – the background
This section explains the background to the citizens’ jury, sets out the values and principles they came up with, describes the citizens’ evaluations of the process and presents a short conclusion.
A group of citizens was randomly selected from the southwest of Western Australia from the electoral roll (but additionally with two Aboriginal people chosen separately). About 30 of these people expressed interest. These were whittled down to 13. The process ensured a good mix of age, gender and geographical location.
The purpose of the jury was to allow the local health service, the South West Area Health Service (SWAHS), to tap into the community’s preferences for the principles and values they wanted to underpin the local health service’s decision making.
The jury was brought together for an evening mainly to ‘break the ice’ and to be given a little more information about what was involved in the jury process. They were asked to consider themselves as being citizens of the southwest – not from Bridgetown or Albany and not bringing their own personal baggage with them. Primarily, however, the evening session involved socialising over a meal.
The jury was also given an example of principles but deliberately not from the health sector as this might have influenced them in their choice of principles. Education was used and principles such as preparation for the workforce, advancing academic standards, and being good citizens were presented and discussed.
On the following morning the citizens were reminded that they were to act as citizens of the southwest. They were told that what they came up with would be used first as the basis of the deliberation at the health forum on the subsequent two days and thereafter as the values foundations on which SWAHS would plan in future. In these two contexts their findings were to be sacrosanct.
They were then presented with information by ‘experts’ (senior SWAHS staff) on the health of the people in the southwest and relevant demographics, the services currently available, the resources available and their current deployment, safety and quality issues, and the organisational and other constraints that SWAHS faces. They were also given the opportunity to quiz the experts who presented the information.
It was clear that some of these ‘experts’, in this case bureaucrats, struggled with the idea that citizens’ values should count. The CEO championed the idea, which left his fellow bureaucrats having to comply with the process and indeed the values. It is around such issues that a strong champion for citizens’ juries is necessary.
Thereafter the jurists were given time to reflect and discuss as a group what principles and values they wanted to underpin the decision making of SWAHS. They then came up with a list of these principles and values, set out below.
Finally, the jury endorsed the principle of involving the community in establishing the principles and values on which SWAHS should base its decision making. They were very much in favour of the principle of informed citizens setting the principles.
The principles and values of decision making in healthcare
Fairness
The principle on which the citizens placed most weight was fairness (equity). They defined this in terms of equal access for equal need, where equal access would involve equal opportunity to use health services. The barriers to using health services were seen as many and included money, distance and racism. Equal access was seen to arise where people perceived the barriers they faced to be equally high; need was taken to be capacity to benefit (i.e. how much good could be done?) and benefits to disadvantaged people were to be weighted more highly (e.g. higher weighted health gains for Aboriginal people) as a form of positive discrimination.
They had a particular concern for those people who were most disadvantaged, especially the health of Aboriginal people.
At the same time the jury acknowledged that there can be a trade-off or competition between equity and efficiency. They felt that from what they had heard from the experts, the existing balance between the two would be improved if more weight, especially geographically, were placed on efficiency and less on equity.
Efficiency
Efficiency was seen by the jury in two ways: first in terms of doing things as well but more cheaply or doing more with the same resources; and second it was about doing as much good as possible (benefit maximisation) with the resources available.
The citizens were of a view that the second type of efficiency needed more emphasis, that is, there needed to be more consideration given to priority setting across different programs. For example should SWAHS spend more on maternity care even if that meant less on care of the elderly?
With one notable exception they were less inclined to argue for higher priorities and increased spending for certain specific areas than for ensuring that such priority setting was done explicitly. The exception was services for the mentally ill.
Where they would have made savings if these had to be made was through hospital rationalisation. They believed that the existing deployment of resources to and in hospitals and emergency departments was potentially inefficient and asked that SWAHS examine ways to rationalise these. They suggested for example that some of the hospital buildings might be converted into aged care facilities or used to provide services for the mentally ill.
Trust with respect to safety
A third principle or set of principles related to quality, safety and risk management. In this context their strategy could be condensed to what amounted to one of trust. They trusted SWAHS to ‘take care of’ these issues on behalf of the southwest community.
Prevention
The next principle was prevention. They wanted a higher priority for prevention but sought to emphasise the need to target prevention activities and ensure that health service resources for prevention were then used efficiently and did result in ‘value added’. By this they meant that, where other organisations (e.g. the Cancer Council, Heart Foundation) were already involved in prevention, SWAHS should avoid duplication and concentrate on prevention that would not otherwise be pursued.
In discussing health promotion within the context of prevention they saw the objective of such health promotion as being about promoting informed choices on health issues.
Self-sufficiency
This area sends some of its patients to Perth, which is the capital of Western Australia, with major tertiary level hospitals. Given that for some patients there is choice between treating them locally or sending them to Perth, the question arises then as to the extent to which this should occur. Is there a desire for greater self-sufficiency in the southwest? On this principle, the citizens had no strong views but felt that total self-sufficiency did not make sense. They argued simply that the extent of self-sufficiency must and should vary by condition.
Holistic care
The jury expressed concerns about practising medicine and treatment in terms of ‘body parts’ medicine and saw an increasing role for holistic health. In this context they considered the Aboriginal Community Controlled Health Organisation (ACCHO) type model as being a useful one for all patients and not just Aboriginal people (Mawson et al 2007). This model seeks to reflect the preferences of Aboriginal people for health and in turn health services to be seen as whole of body health and healthcare.
Transparency and accountability
The citizens supported transparency and accountability in decision making in SWAHS. They saw the holding of the citizens’ jury as an indication of a willingness on the part of senior management at SWAHS to attempt to be transparent and to boost accountability to the public.
Community values
Finally the jury endorsed the principle of involving the community in establishing the principles and values on which SWAHS should base its decision making. They were very much in favour of the principle of informed citizens setting the principles.
Citizens’ evaluation
After the event the participating citizens were mailed a questionnaire asking them to evaluate various aspects of the jury process. Most responded by mail; four were interviewed by phone. There was thus a 100% response. The general response of the citizens to the jury process was one of satisfaction, approval and enthusiasm. More specifically:
▪ With respect to information most but not all agreed with the decision not to provide advance reading. Nonetheless, overall more information would have been better. It seems that it is with respect to the amount of information where things might be improved rather than with respect to the type of information.
▪ The time allotted for the jury’s deliberations, from 9am to 4pm in the one day, was for some rather too little, for others about right. No one argued that it was too long.
▪ Several points were made with respect to what was thought to be the best aspect of the whole process, and insofar as anything emerged as a general picture, it seems to have been the opportunity to have been involved in the group process. No picture emerged of what the worst aspect was.
Summing up citizens’ juries
The overall conclusion of the organisers was that the citizens’ jury had been a success. The participants were able to act as citizens and were comfortable to play this role; they believed they do have a role to play in health service decision making; they were able to reach a consensus on a clear set of values and principles; and they felt the process was enjoyable and worthwhile. Perhaps the key findings beyond that are that they wanted more resources for prevention, more for Aboriginal health and more for the mentally ill. Forgoing spending on hospitals and emergency departments was their way of freeing the resources for SWAHS to be able to pay for these extras which they sought.
It is relevant to note that in the subsequent forum the values and principles that the jury developed were overwhelmingly endorsed by the members of the forum.
Experiences with the four citizens’ juries that the author has facilitated in Western Australia suggest that the people on the jury very much like the idea of being given the role of citizens (Mooney 2007). It is worthy of note that they seemed to see this as being rather novel and they embraced the role with great enthusiasm. All the juries were of the view that one of the best aspects of the system was being given the opportunity to sit with other citizens, to be able to express their views in a structured way and to have their voices heard.
Conclusion
The voice of citizens in decision making and priority setting in health is essential because budgets are finite and means must be found to allocate available resources rationally. Community participation in healthcare is advantageous in delivering more efficient healthcare and more broadly in assisting to enhance democracy. For the first, efficiency is more likely to come from allocative efficiency than from operational (i.e. technical) efficiency. It can lead to better allocation of resources in the sense of doing more social good. It can create an environment where there is more debate about the objectives and goals of the system. The sort of community consultation that is likely to prove most fruitful is that which emphasises citizens acting in the role of setting principles and values to underpin healthcare delivery. Here objectives and goals which are too often just assumed or implied can be held up to public scrutiny and if desired changed.
The enhancement of democracy is no small advantage but certainly cannot be achieved if it is only the health sector where citizens’ juries are used. At this level there needs to be a more general consideration of the relationship between the voice of the people and the nature of our social institutions. It is here that examination is required of how to manage the plurality of interests and grapple with balancing power in decision making. Democracy can be thick or thin or anywhere in between. Increasingly we are faced with a thinner and thinner version in Australia. Community consultations used honestly and genuinely to allow the voice of the informed people to be heard more is a way to thicken democracy and our democratic institutions, including in healthcare. Managing clinical processes will only be effective if the ‘right’ healthcare decisions are being made. Healthcare decisions that respond to community needs and preferences are those that this chapter seeks to address.
References
Anderson, E., Value in Ethics and Economics. (1993) Harvard University Press, Cambridge.
Boswell, J., Community and the Economy. (1990) The Theory of Public Cooperation, Routledge, London.
Glasner, P., Rights or rituals? Why juries can do more harm than good, Participatory Learning and Action Notes 40 (2001); IIED.
Honigsbaum, F.; Richards, J.; Lockett, T., Priority Setting in Action Health Services Management Centre, Birmingham. (1995) Radcliffe Medical Press, Oxford.
Kashefi, E.; Mort, M., ‘Grounded Citizens’ Juries: A Tool for Health Activism?Health Expectations 7 (2004) 1–13.
Little, M., Ethonomics: the ethics of the unaffordable, Archives of Surgery 135 (2000) 17–21.
McIver, S., Healthy debate? An independent evaluation of citizens’ juries in health settings. (1998) Kings Fund, London.
McPherson, C.B., The Life and Times of Liberal Democracy. (1977) Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Mooney, G., Evidence-based medicine: objectives and values, In: (Editors: InKristiansen, I.S.; Mooney, G.) Evidence Based Medicine. In its Place (2004) Routledge, London.
Mooney, G.; Blackwell, S., Whose health service is it anyway?Medical Journal of Australia 180 (2004) 76–78.
Muller, J.Z., The Mind and the Market. (2003) Anchor Books, New York.
Olsen, J.-A.; Donaldson, C., Helicopters, hearts and hips: Using willingness to pay to set priorities for public sector healthcare programmes, Social Science and Medicine 46 (1998) 1–12.
Robinson, J., Consumers’ sovereignty in a planned economy, In: (Editors: Nove, A.; Nuti, D.M.) Socialist Economics (1972) Penguin, Harmondsworth.
Sen, A., Inequality re-examined. (1992) Clarendon Press, Oxford.
Taylor, C., Sources of the Self. The Making of the Modern Identity. (1989) Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Vuori, H., Overview – community participation in primary healthcare: a means or end? IV. International Congress of the World Federation of Public Health Associations, Public Health Review 12 (1984) 331–339.
World Health Organization, Report of the Expert Committee on the Health Education of the Public. Technical Report Series 89. (1954) WHO, Geneva.