Ethical Controversies in Pediatric Critical Care

Published on 22/03/2015 by admin

Filed under Critical Care Medicine

Last modified 22/03/2015

Print this page

rate 1 star rate 2 star rate 3 star rate 4 star rate 5 star
Your rating: none, Average: 0 (0 votes)

This article have been viewed 1378 times

217 Ethical Controversies in Pediatric Critical Care

As the field of pediatric critical care medicine continues to evolve, ethical concerns in the care of the critically ill child remain of profound concern to all practitioners. This area of pediatric critical care medicine demands the same high level of knowledge and competence as all other areas of critical care practice. Many troubling issues in the pediatric intensive care unit (PICU) revolve around end-of-life decision making and palliative patient management. In this chapter, we explore both issues.

image Decision Making in the Pediatric Intensive Care Unit

Role Of Parents And Physicians

Who should make the final decision about treatment for a child in the PICU? In the United States, the clear consensus in the fields of ethics and the law is that a competent adult patient has the right to refuse all forms of medical therapy, including life-sustaining treatment, even if it is certain that such a refusal will hasten death. A similar moral and legal consensus holds that parents have the authority to determine the best interests of their children and make decisions in accord with their own values. However, pediatric healthcare providers also have legal and ethical duties to their patients, independent of parental desires or proxy consent.13

How can one objectively assess whether a decision is within the range of acceptable ethical choices for a child? More than 20 years ago, a widely respected decision-making framework for children in the PICU context was published by the President’s Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research.4 The commission proposed five considerations for determining a child’s “best interests” and therefore the appropriate approach when weighing different treatment options: (1) the amount of suffering and the potential for relief, (2) the severity of dysfunction and the potential for restoration of function, (3) the expected duration of life, (4) the potential for personal satisfaction and enjoyment of life, and (5) the possibility of developing a capacity for self-determination. The commission then advocated applying these criteria based on an assessment of the proposed treatment plan as clearly beneficial, ambiguous or uncertain, or futile. The commission concluded that in most circumstances, the child’s parents should be the final decision makers on all medical decisions (Table 217-1). The Committee on Bioethics of the American Academy of Pediatrics has similarly recommended great deference to patents’ informed decisions.5

TABLE 217-1 Decision Making in the Pediatric Intensive Care Unit

Physician’s Assessment of Treatment Option Parents Prefer to Accept Treatment Parents Prefer to Forgo Treatment
Clearly beneficial Provide treatment Provide treatment (during review process)
Ambiguous/uncertain Provide treatment Forgo treatment
Futile Provide treatment (unless provider prefers not to) Forgo treatment

The President’s Commission also concluded, reflecting the legal consensus in this area, that parental authority must occasionally be superseded by clinicians when it is determined that the parents’ decisions are at odds with the societal consensus about a child’s interests or when parents’ actions produce certain risk or harm to the child. If life-threatening choices are not involved, or if the risk of substantial harm is minimal, courts have generally respected the decisions of the parents, even though physicians may have disagreed strongly. In some states, parents are legally permitted to refuse standard immunizations for religious reasons.5 As the potential threat to the child increases, however, and as the benefits of treatment become more certain, actions to override parental choices are not only legally supportable but also mandatory in most jurisdictions. Numerous court opinions have upheld the notion, first pronounced in the 1944 Supreme court case of Prince v. Massachusetts, that a parent may make a martyr of himself because of religious convictions, “but he is not free to make a martyr of his child.”6

Need For Improved Communication

A growing body of research reveals that parents report problems related to optimal communication as one of the major deficiencies in the end-of-life care provided to their child. Consistently effective communication from one level of care and one set of providers to the next is a basic expectation, but one that is often not fully met.7 Meert and colleagues reported on the experience of the bereaved parents of 48 children cared for at 6 PICUs in the United States.8 These investigators found that the most common communication issue identified by parents was the physicians’ availability and attentiveness to their informational needs. More important than the actual outcome, recent data also suggest that many parents want more involvement in end-of-life planning, from discussions around the location of death to even consideration of a plan for extubation at home. These data suggest that the potential for strained communications is mitigated if clinicians provide timely clinical and prognostic information and support the family with a comfortable setting and continuous psychosocial support.

Determining Futility

Few issues have provoked as much controversy as the notion of futility. Who should determine when a situation is futile? A recent review of the futility debate noted that the debate about how to resolve cases in which patients and families demand interventions clinicians regard as futile has been in evolution over the past 20 years.9 The first generation was characterized by attempts by physicians to define futility in terms of certain clinical criteria. These attempts failed because they proposed limitations to care based on value judgments for which there is no consensus. The second generation was based on a procedural approach that empowered hospitals, through their ethics committees, to decide whether interventions demanded by families were futile. Many hospitals adopted such policies, and some states such as Texas incorporated this approach into legislation. This approach has also not succeeded because it gives hospitals authority to decide whether or not to accede to demands clinicians regard as unreasonable when any national consensus on what is a “beneficial treatment” remains under intense debate. Absent such a consensus, it appears that procedural mechanisms to resolve futility disputes inevitably confront the same insurmountable barriers as attempts to define futility.

The Society for Critical Care Medicine (SCCM) states that treatments should be defined as futile “only when they will not accomplish their intended goal.”10 Moreover, this official position on futility states:

This approach advocates that the local community draft procedures to be followed in cases of dispute, with broad input from the community instead of ad hoc attempts at the bedside to define and resolve differences over futility. This policy goes on to state:

The Committee on Bioethics for the American Academy of Pediatrics has published guidelines articulating similar sentiments.2